of an uneasy conscience; he went in spite of foreseen
pain and the allurement of possible pleasure.
When a man endures privations for the sake of posthumous
fame, it is not that he expects to enjoy that fame
when it comes, or expects others to enjoy it; he is
simply so made that he cannot resist the sway of that
ambition which will bring him no good. The pursuit
of pleasure is a sophisticated impulse which appears
in marked degree only in a few self-conscious and
idle individuals. William James gave the deathblow
to this pleasure-seeking psychology. “Important
as is the influence of pleasures and pains upon our
movements, they are far from being our only stimuli.
With the manifestations of instinct and emotional expression,
for example, they have absolutely nothing to do.
Who smiles for the pleasure of smiling, or frowns
for the pleasure of the frown? Who blushes to
escape the discomfort of not blushing? Or who
in anger, grief, or fear is actuated to the movements
which he makes by the pleasures which they yield?
In all these cases the movements are discharged fatally
by the vis a tergo which the stimulus exerts upon a
nervous system framed to respond in just that way.
The impulsive quality of mental states is
an attribute behind which we cannot go.” [Footnote:
W. James, Psychology, vol. II, p. 550.] It is
not true, then, that love of pleasure and fear of
pain are the universal motives. It is not true
that we inevitably act along the line of least hedonic
resistance, that pain necessarily veers us off and
pleasure irresistibly attracts. By force of will,
by “suggestion” or training, we can go
directly counter to the pull of pleasure. It
is true that we should not have the instincts and
habits and impulses that we do were they not in general
useful for our existence or happiness. But the
evolutionary process has been clumsy; we are not properly
adjusted; we become the victims of ideas fixes; ideas
and activities obsess us quite without relation to
their hedonic value. So pleasure and pain are
not usually the impelling force or conscious motive
behind conduct. What they are is-the touchstone,
the criterion, the justification.
We do not act in ways that bring the greatest happiness, but we ought to. We do not consciously seek happiness, and we ought not to. We ought to continue to care for things and for ideals; but the things and ideals we care and work for ought to be such that through them man’s welfare is advanced.
Are pleasures and pains incommensurable?
An objection commonly raised is that pleasures and pains of various sorts are incommensurable; that therefore no calculation of relative advantage is possible; and that the eudaemonistie criterion for action is thereby made impracticable and useless.