in thy Logic-mill hast an earthly mechanism for the
Godlike itself, and wouldst fain grind me out Virtuefrom
the husks of Pleasure, I tell thee, Nay! Is the
heroic inspiration we name Virtue but some Passion,
some bubble of the blood, bubbling in the direction
others
profit by? I know not; only this I
know, If what thou namest Happiness be our true aim,
then are we all astray. ‘Happy,’ my
brother? First of all, what difference is it
whether thou art happy or not! ‘Happiness
our being’s end and aim,’ all that very
paltry speculation is at bottom, if we will count
well, not yet two centuries old in the world”
[Footnote: Sartor Resartus: “The Everlasting
No” Past and Present: “Happy”
Leaving aside this last statement, which is an irrelevant
untruth, we probably feel an instinctive sympathy with
Carlyle, and a sort of shame that we should have thought
of happiness as the goal of conduct. Carlyle
goes so far in his tirades as to call our happiness-morality
a “pig philosophy,” which makes the universe
out to be a huge “swine’s trough”
from which mankind is trying to get the maximum “pigs”
wash. Again he calls it a “Mechanical Profit-and-Loss
theory” In such picturesque language he embodies
a point of view which in milder terms has been expressed
by many.] But to say that we must often oppose inclination
in the name of duty is by no means to say that we
must do what in the end will make against happiness.
The trouble with inclination and passion is precisely
that they are often ruiners of happiness. The
very real and frequent opposition of desire and duty
is no support of the view that duty is irrelevant
to happiness, but quite consistent with the rational
account of morality-that dates at least back to the
ancient Greeks-which shows it to be the means to man’s
most lasting and widespread happiness.
Must we deny that duty is the servant of happiness?
We may go on to point out various flaws in the doctrine,
of which Carlyle is one of the extreme representatives,
that the account of morality as a means to happiness
is immoral and leads to shocking results.
(1) The plausibility of the doctrine rests largely
on its confusion with the very different truth that
we should not make happiness our conscious aim.
It is one of the surest fruits of experience that
happiness is best won by forgetting it; he that loses
his life shall truly find it. To think much of
happiness slides inevitably over into thinking too
much of present happiness, and more of one’s
own than others’ happiness; it leads to what
Spencer properly dubs “the pursuit of happiness
without regard to the conditions by fulfillment of
which happiness is to be achieved.” Carlyle
is practically on the right track in bidding us think
rather of duty, of work, of accomplishment. But
that is far from denying that these aims have their
ultimate justification in the happiness they forward.
In order that remote ends may be attained, it is often
necessary to cease thinking of them and concentrate