of death in battle, we know, recalls to many, with
extreme vividness, scenes of early childhood which
they had deemed long since forgotten. “There
is nothing,” says Bergson, “more instructive
in this regard than what happens in cases of sudden
suffocation—in men drowned or hanged.
The man, when brought to life again, states that he
saw in a very short time all the forgotten events
of his life, passing before him with great rapidity,
with their smallest circumstances, and in the very
order in which they occurred."[Footnote: La Perception
du Changement, pp. 30-31, and Matter and Memory, p
200 (Fr p 168).] Hence we can never be absolutely
sure that we have forgotten anything although at any
given time we may be unable to recall it to mind.
There is an unconscious memory.[Footnote: Cf.
Samuel Butler’s Unconscious Memory.] Speaking
of the profound and yet undeniable reality of the
unconscious, Bergson says,[Footnote: Matter and
Memory, pp 181-182 (Fr. pp. 152-153). See also
Le Souvenir du present et la fausse reconnaissance,
Revue philosophique, Dec., 1908, p. 592, and L’Energie
spirituelle, pp. 159- 161 (Mind-Energy).] “Our
unwillingness to conceive unconscious psychical states,
is due, above all, to the fact that we hold consciousness
to be the essential property of psychical states,
so that a psychical state cannot, it seems, cease
to be conscious without ceasing to exist. But
if consciousness is but the characteristic note of
the present, that is to say, of the actually lived,
in short, of the active, then that which does not
act may cease to belong to consciousness without therefore
ceasing to exist in some manner. In other words,
in the psychological domain, consciousness may not
be the synonym of existence, but only of real action
or of immediate efficacy; limiting thus the meaning
of the term, we shall have less difficulty in representing
to ourselves a psychical state which is unconscious,
that is to say, ineffective. Whatever idea we
may frame of consciousness in itself, such as it would
be if it could work untrammelled, we cannot deny that
in a being which has bodily functions, the chief office
of consciousness is to preside over action and to
enlighten choice. Therefore it throws light on
the immediate antecedents of the decision and on those
past recollections which can usefully combine with
it; all else remains in shadow.” But we
have no more right to say that the past effaces itself
as soon as perceived than to suppose that material
objects cease to exist when we cease to perceive them.
Memory, to use a geometrical illustration which Bergson
himself employs, comes into action like the point of
a cone pressing against a plane. The plane denotes
the present need, particularly in relation to bodily
action, while the cone stands for all our total past.
Much of this past, indeed most of it, only endures
as unconscious Memory, but it is always capable of
coming to the apex of the cone, i.e., coming
into consciousness. So we may say that there are
different planes of Memory, conic sections, if we keep
up the original metaphor, and the largest of these
contains all our past. This may be well described
as “the plane of dream."[Footnote: See Matter
and Memory, p. 222 (Fr. p. 186) and the paper L’Effort
intellectuel, Revue philosophique, Jan., 1902, pp.
2 and 25, L’Energie spirituelle, pp. 165 and
199 (Mind-Energy).]