that prosperity is always proportioned to good conduct,
nor yet merely because it contributes nothing to the
establishment of morality—since it is quite
a different thing to make a prosperous man and a good
man, or to make one prudent and sharp-sighted for
his own interests, and to make him virtuous—but
because the springs it provides for morality are such
as rather undermine it and destroy its sublimity,
since they put the motives to virtue and to vice in
the same class, and only teach us to make a better
calculation, the specific difference between virtue
and vice being entirely extinguished. On the
other hand, as to moral feeling, this supposed special
sense [Footnote: I class the principle of moral
feeling under that of happiness, because every empirical
interest promises to contribute to our well-being
by the agreeableness that a thing affords, whether
it be immediately and without a view to profit, or
whether profit be regarded. We must likewise,
with Hutcheson, class the principle of sympathy with
the happiness of others under his assumed moral sense.]
the appeal to it is indeed superficial when those
who cannot
think believe that
feeling will
help them out, even in what concerns general laws:
and besides, feelings which naturally differ infinitely
in degree cannot furnish a uniform standard of good
and evil, nor has anyone a right to form judgments
for others by his own feelings: nevertheless this
moral feeling is nearer to morality and its dignity
in this respect, that it pays virtue the honour of
ascribing to her
immediately the satisfaction
and esteem we have for her, and does not, as it were,
tell her to her face that we are not attached to her
by her beauty but by profit.
Amongst the rational principles of morality,
the ontological conception of perfection, notwithstanding
its defects, is better than the theological conception
which derives morality from a Divine absolutely perfect
will. The former is, no doubt, empty and indefinite,
and consequently useless for finding in the boundless
field of possible reality the greatest amount suitable
for us; moreover, in attempting to distinguish specifically
the reality of which we are now speaking from every
other, it inevitably tends to turn in a circle, and
cannot avoid tacitly presupposing the morality which
it is to explain; it is nevertheless preferable to
the theological view, first, because we have no intuition
of the Divine perfection, and can only deduce it from
our own conceptions, the most important of which is
that of morality, and our explanation would thus be
involved in a gross circle; and, in the next place,
if we avoid this, the only notion of the Divine will
remaining to us is a conception made up of the attributes
of desire of glory and dominion, combined with the
awful conceptions of might and vengeance, and any
system of morals erected on this foundation would
be directly opposed to morality.