wishes and wills. The reason of this is that all
the elements which belong to the notion of happiness
are altogether empirical, i. e. they must be borrowed
from experience, and nevertheless the idea of happiness
requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in
my present and all future circumstances. Now
it is impossible that the most clear-sighted, and at
the same time most powerful being (supposed finite),
should frame to himself a definite conception of what
he really wills in this. Does he will riches,
how much anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby
draw upon his shoulders? Does he will knowledge
and discernment, perhaps it might prove to be only
an eye so much the sharper to show him so much the
more fearfully the evils that are now concealed from
him, and that cannot be avoided, or to impose more
wants on his desires, which already give him concern
enough. Would he have long life, who guarantees
to him that it would not be a long misery? would he
at least have health? how often has uneasiness of
the body restrained from excesses into which perfect
health would have allowed one to fall? and so on.
In short he is unable, on any principle, to determine
with certainty what would make him truly happy; because
to do so he would need to be omniscient. We cannot
therefore act on any definite principles to secure
happiness, but only on empirical counsels, ex. gr.
of regimen, frugality, courtesy, reserve, &c., which
experience teaches do, on the average, most promote
well-being. Hence it follows that the imperatives
of prudence do not, strictly speaking, command at
all, that is, they cannot present actions objectively
as practically necessary; that they are rather to
be regarded as counsels (consilia) than precepts (praecepta)
of reason, that the problem to determine certainly
and universally what action would promote the happiness
of a rational being is completely insoluble, and consequently
no imperative respecting it is possible which should,
in the strict sense, command to do what makes happy;
because happiness is not an ideal of reason but of
imagination, resting solely on empirical grounds,
and it is vain to expect that these should define
an action by which one could attain the totality of
a series of consequences which is really endless.
This imperative of prudence would however be an analytical
proposition if we assume that the means to happiness
could be certainly assigned; for it is distinguished
from the imperative of skill only by this, that in
the latter the end is merely possible, in the former
it is given; as however both only ordain the means
to that which we suppose to be willed as an end, it
follows that the imperative which ordains the willing
of the means to him who wills the end is in both cases
analytical. Thus there is no difficulty in regard
to the possibility of an imperative of this kind either.