what is good, what bad, conformably to duty or inconsistent
with it, if, without in the least teaching them anything
new, we only, like Socrates, direct their attention
to the principle they themselves employ; and that therefore
we do not need science and philosophy to know what
we should do to be honest and good, yea, even wise
and virtuous. Indeed we might well have conjectured
beforehand that the knowledge of what every man is
bound to do, and therefore also to know, would be within
the reach of every man, even the commonest. [Footnote:
Compare the note to the Preface to the Critique of
the Practical Reason, p. 111. A specimen of Kant’s
proposed application of the Socratic method may be
found in Mr. Semple’a translation of the Metaphysic
of Ethics, p. 290.] Here we cannot forbear admiration
when we see how great an advantage the practical judgment
has over the theoretical in the common understanding
of men. In the latter, if common reason ventures
to depart from the laws of experience and from the
perceptions of the senses it falls into mere inconceivabilities
and self-contradictions, at least into chaos of uncertainty,
obscurity, and instability. But in the practical
sphere it is just when the common understanding excludes
all sensible springs from practical laws that its
power of judgment begins to show itself to advantage.
It then becomes even subtle, whether it be that it
chicanes with its own conscience or with other claims
respecting what is to be called right, or whether
it desires for its own instruction to determine honestly
the worth of actions; and, in the latter case, it
may even have as good a hope of hitting the mark as
any philosopher whatever can promise himself.
Nay, it is almost more sure of doing so, because the
philosopher cannot have any other principle, while
he may easily perplex his judgment by a multitude of
considerations foreign to the matter, and so turn
aside from the right way. Would it not therefore
be wiser in moral concerns to acquiesce in the judgment
of common reason or at most only to call in philosophy
for the purpose of rendering the system of morals more
complete and intelligible, and its rules more convenient
for use (especially for disputation), but not so as
to draw off the common understanding from its happy
simplicity, or to bring it by means of philosophy
into a new path of inquiry and instruction?
Innocence is indeed a glorious thing, only, on the other hand, it is very sad that it cannot well maintain itself, and is easily seduced. On this account even wisdom—which otherwise consists more in conduct than in knowledge—yet has need of science, not in order to learn from it, but to secure for its precepts admission and permanence. Against all the commands of duty which reason represents to man as so deserving of respect, he feels in himself a powerful counterpoise in his wants and inclinations, the entire satisfaction of which he sums up under the name of happiness. Now reason issues its