closely touching our most precious freedoms.”
Keyishian v. Bd. of Regents of the Univ. of the
State of N.Y., 385 U.S. 589, 603 (1967) (internal
quotation marks and citation omitted); see also Bantam
Books, Inc. v. Sullivan, 372 U.S. 58, 66 (1963)
("The separation of legitimate from illegitimate speech
calls for sensitive tools.”) (internal quotation
marks and citation omitted). Where the government
draws content-based restrictions on speech in order
to advance a compelling government interest, the First
Amendment demands the precision of a scalpel, not
a sledgehammer. We believe that a public library’s
use of the technology protection measures mandated
by CIPA is not narrowly tailored to further the governmental
interests at stake. Although the strength of
different libraries’ interests in blocking certain
forms of speech may vary from library to library,
depending on the frequency and severity of problems
experienced by each particular library, we conclude,
based on our findings of fact, that any public library’s
use of a filtering product mandated by CIPA will necessarily
fail to be narrowly tailored to address the library’s
legitimate interests. Because it is impossible
for a public library to comply with CIPA without blocking
substantial amounts of speech whose suppression serves
no legitimate state interest, we therefore hold that
CIPA is facially invalid, even under the more stringent
standard of facial invalidity urged on us by the government,
which would require upholding CIPA if it is possible
for just a single library to comply with CIPA’s
conditions without violating the First Amendment.
See supra Part
iii. 3. Less Restrictive
Alternatives
The constitutional infirmity of a public library’s
use of software filters is evidenced not only by the
absence of narrow tailoring, but also by the existence
of less restrictive alternatives that further the
government’s legitimate interests. See
Playboy, 529 U.S. at 813 ("If a less restrictive alternative
would serve the Government’s purpose, the legislature
must use that alternative."); Sable, 492 U.S. at 126
("The Government may . . . regulate the content of
constitutionally protected speech in order to promote
a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive
means to further the articulated interest.").
As is the case with the narrow tailoring requirement,
the government bears the burden of proof in showing
the ineffectiveness of less restrictive alternatives.
“When a plausible, less restrictive alternative
is offered to a content-based speech restriction,
it is the Government’s obligation to prove that
the alternative will be ineffective to achieve its
goals.” Playboy, 529 U.S. at 816; see also
Reno, 521 U.S. at 879 ("The breadth of this content-based
restriction of speech imposes an especially heavy
burden on the Government to explain why a less restrictive
provision would not be as effective . . . ."); Fabulous
Assocs., Inc. v. Pa. Pub. Util.
Comm’n, 896 F.2d 780, 787 (3d Cir. 1990) ("We
focus . . . on the more difficult question whether
the Commonwealth has borne its heavy burden of demonstrating
that the compelling state interest could not be served
by restrictions that are less intrusive on protected
forms of expression.”) (internal quotation marks
and citation omitted).