Montreal, for May, 1904.] that our trust is at any
rate
untrue when it is made,
i. e; before the action; and I seem to remember that
he disposes of anything like a faith in the general
excellence of the universe (making the faithful person’s
part in it at any rate more excellent) as a ‘lie
in the soul.’ But the pathos of this expression
should not blind us to the complication of the facts.
I doubt whether Professor Taylor would himself be
in favor of practically handling trusters of these
kinds as liars. Future and present really mix
in such emergencies, and one can always escape lies
in them by using hypothetic forms. But Mr. Taylor’s
attitude suggests such absurd possibilities of practice
that it seems to me to illustrate beautifully how self-stultifying
the conception of a truth that shall merely register
a standing fixture may become. Theoretic truth,
truth of passive copying, sought in the sole interests
of copying as such, not because copying is
good
for something, but because copying ought
schlechthin to be, seems, if you look at it coldly,
to be an almost preposterous ideal. Why should
the universe, existing in itself, also exist in copies?
How
can it be copied in the solidity of its objective
fulness? And even if it could, what would the
motive be? ‘Even the hairs of your head
are numbered.’ Doubtless they are, virtually;
but why, as an absolute proposition,
ought the
number to become copied and known? Surely knowing
is only one way of interacting with reality and adding
to its effect.
The opponent here will ask: ’Has not the
knowing of truth any substantive value on its own
account, apart from the collateral advantages it may
bring? And if you allow theoretic satisfactions
to exist at all, do they not crowd the collateral
satisfactions out of house and home, and must not
pragmatism go into bankruptcy, if she admits them
at all?’ The destructive force of such talk disappears
as soon as we use words concretely instead of abstractly,
and ask, in our quality of good pragmatists, just
what the famous theoretic needs are known as and in
what the intellectual satisfactions consist.
Are they not all mere matters of consistency—and
emphatically not of consistency between an absolute
reality and the mind’s copies of it, but of
actually felt consistency among judgments, objects,
and habits of reacting, in the mind’s own experienceable
world? And are not both our need of such consistency
and our pleasure in it conceivable as outcomes of
the natural fact that we are beings that do develop
mental habits—habit itself proving
adaptively beneficial in an environment where the
same objects, or the same kinds of objects, recur
and follow ‘law’? If this were so,
what would have come first would have been the collateral
profits of habit as such, and the theoretic life would
have grown up in aid of these. In point of fact,
this seems to have been the probable case. At