the rapid flights of fancy, or the strong movements
of passion. That is, he was to the poet what
the painter of still life is to the painter of history.
Common sense sympathizes with the impressions of things
on ordinary minds in ordinary circumstances:
genius catches the glancing combinations presented
to the eye of fancy, under the influence of passion.
It is the province of the didactic reasoner to take
cognizance of those results of human nature which
are constantly repeated and always the same, which
follow one another in regular succession, which are
acted upon by large classes of men, and embodied in
received customs, laws, language, and institutions;
and it was in arranging, comparing, and arguing on
these kind of general results, that Johnson’s
excellence lay. But he could not quit his hold
of the commonplace and mechanical, and apply the general
rule to the particular exception, or show how the
nature of man was modified by the workings of passion,
or the infinite fluctuations of thought and accident.
Hence he could judge neither of the heights nor depths
of poetry. Nor is this all; for being conscious
of great powers in himself, and those powers of an
adverse tendency to those of his author, he would be
for setting up a foreign jurisdiction over poetry,
and making criticism a kind of Procrustes’ bed
of genius, where he might cut down imagination to
matter-of-fact, regulate the passions according to
reason, and translate the whole into logical diagrams
and rhetorical declamation. Thus he says of Shakespeare’s
characters, in contradiction to what Pope had observed,
and to what every one else feels, that each character
is a species, instead of being an individual.
He in fact found the general species or didactic
form in Shakespeare’s characters, which was
all he sought or cared for; he did not find the individual
traits, or the dramatic distinctions which Shakespeare
has engrafted on this general nature, because he felt
no interest in them. Shakespeare’s bold
and happy flights of imagination were equally thrown
away upon our author. He was not only without
any particular fineness of organic sensibility, alive
to all the ‘mighty world of ear and eye’,
which is necessary to the painter or musician, but
without that intenseness of passion, which, seeking
to exaggerate whatever excites the feelings of pleasure
or power in the mind, and moulding the impressions
of natural objects according to the impulses of imagination,
produces a genius and a taste for poetry. According
to Dr. Johnson, a mountain is sublime, or a rose is
beautiful; for that their name and definition imply.
But he would no more be able to give the description
of Dover cliff in Lear, or the description of flowers
in The Winter’s Tale, than to describe the objects
of a sixth sense; nor do we think he would have any
very profound feeling of the beauty of the passages
here referred to. A stately common-place, such
as Congreve’s description of a ruin in The Mourning
Bride, would have answered Johnson’s purpose
just as well, or better than the first; and an indiscriminate
profusion of scents and hues would have interfered
less with the ordinary routine of his imagination than
Perdita’s lines, which seem enamoured of their
own sweetness—