of thinking that I have often said, when consulted
by despairing sanitary reformers, that what London
needs to make her healthy is an earthquake. Why,
then, it may be asked, do not I, as a public-spirited
man, employ incendiaries to set it on fire, with a
heroic disregard of the consequences to myself and
others? Any vivisector would, if he had the courage
of his opinions. The reasonable answer is that
London can be made healthy without burning her down;
and that as we have not enough civic virtue to make
her healthy in a humane and economical way, we should
not have enough to rebuild her in that way. In
the old Hebrew legend, God lost patience with the
world as Nero did with Rome, and drowned everybody
except a single family. But the result was that
the progeny of that family reproduced all the vices
of their predecessors so exactly that the misery caused
by the flood might just as well have been spared:
things went on just as they did before. In the
same way, the lists of diseases which vivisection
claims to have cured is long; but the returns of the
Registrar-General show that people still persist in
dying of them as if vivisection had never been heard
of. Any fool can burn down a city or cut an animal
open; and an exceptionally foolish fool is quite likely
to promise enormous benefits to the race as the result
of such activities. But when the constructive,
benevolent part of the business comes to be done,
the same want of imagination, the same stupidity and
cruelty, the same laziness and want of perseverance
that prevented Nero or the vivisector from devising
or pushing through humane methods, prevents him from
bringing order out of the chaos and happiness out
of the misery he has made. At one time it seemed
reasonable enough to declare that it was impossible
to find whether or not there was a stone inside a
man’s body except by exploring it with a knife,
or to find out what the sun is made of without visiting
it in a balloon. Both these impossibilities have
been achieved, but not by vivisectors. The Rontgen
rays need not hurt the patient; and spectrum analysis
involves no destruction. After such triumphs of
humane experiment and reasoning, it is useless to
assure us that there is no other key to knowledge
except cruelty. When the vivisector offers us
that assurance, we reply simply and contemptuously,
“You mean that you are not clever or humane
or energetic enough to find one.”
CRUELTY FOR ITS OWN SAKE
It will now, I hope, be clear why the attack on vivisection is not an attack on the right to knowledge: why, indeed, those who have the deepest conviction of the sacredness of that right are the leaders of the attack. No knowledge is finally impossible of human attainment; for even though it may be beyond our present capacity, the needed capacity is not unattainable. Consequently no method of investigation is the only method; and no law forbidding any particular method can cut us off from the knowledge we hope to gain by it. The only knowledge we lose by forbidding cruelty is knowledge at first hand of cruelty itself, which is precisely the knowledge humane people wish to be spared.