over himself, who knows how to speak and how to keep
silence, who takes pleasure in subjecting himself
to severity and hardness, and has reverence for all
that is severe and hard. “Wotan placed
a hard heart in my breast,” says an old Scandinavian
Saga: it is thus rightly expressed from the soul
of a proud Viking. Such a type of man is even
proud of not being made for sympathy; the hero of
the Saga therefore adds warningly: “He who
has not a hard heart when young, will never have one.”
The noble and brave who think thus are the furthest
removed from the morality which sees precisely in
sympathy, or in acting for the good of others, or in
DESINTERESSEMENT, the characteristic of the moral;
faith in oneself, pride in oneself, a radical enmity
and irony towards “selflessness,” belong
as definitely to noble morality, as do a careless
scorn and precaution in presence of sympathy and the
“warm heart.”—It is the powerful
who know how to honour, it is their art, their
domain for invention. The profound reverence for
age and for tradition—all law rests on this
double reverence,— the belief and prejudice
in favour of ancestors and unfavourable to newcomers,
is typical in the morality of the powerful; and if,
reversely, men of “modern ideas” believe
almost instinctively in “progress” and
the “future,” and are more and more lacking
in respect for old age, the ignoble origin of these
“ideas” has complacently betrayed itself
thereby. A morality of the ruling class, however,
is more especially foreign and irritating to present-day
taste in the sternness of its principle that one has
duties only to one’s equals; that one may act
towards beings of a lower rank, towards all that is
foreign, just as seems good to one, or “as the
heart desires,” and in any case “beyond
good and evil”: it is here that sympathy
and similar sentiments can have a place. The
ability and obligation to exercise prolonged gratitude
and prolonged revenge—both only within the
circle of equals,— artfulness in retaliation,
RAFFINEMENT of the idea in friendship, a certain necessity
to have enemies (as outlets for the emotions of envy,
quarrelsomeness, arrogance—in fact, in order
to be a good friend): all these are typical
characteristics of the noble morality, which, as has
been pointed out, is not the morality of “modern
ideas,” and is therefore at present difficult
to realize, and also to unearth and disclose.—It
is otherwise with the second type of morality, slave-morality.
Supposing that the abused, the oppressed, the suffering,
the unemancipated, the weary, and those uncertain
of themselves should moralize, what will be the common
element in their moral estimates? Probably a
pessimistic suspicion with regard to the entire situation
of man will find expression, perhaps a condemnation
of man, together with his situation. The slave
has an unfavourable eye for the virtues of the powerful;
he has a skepticism and distrust, a refinement
of distrust of everything “good” that is