striving after reciprocal adaptation. Society
will therefore be suspicious of all
inelasticity
of character, of mind and even of body, because it
is the possible sign of a slumbering activity as well
as of an activity with separatist tendencies, that
inclines to swerve from the common centre round which
society gravitates: in short, because it is the
sign of an eccentricity. And yet, society cannot
intervene at this stage by material repression, since
it is not affected in a material fashion. It
is confronted with something that makes it uneasy,
but only as a symptom—scarcely a threat,
at the very most a gesture. A gesture, therefore,
will be its reply. Laughter must be something
of this kind, a sort of
social gesture.
By the fear which it inspires, it restrains eccentricity,
keeps constantly awake and in mutual contact certain
activities of a secondary order which might retire
into their shell and go to sleep, and, in short, softens
down whatever the surface of the social body may retain
of mechanical inelasticity. Laughter, then, does
not belong to the province of esthetics alone, since
unconsciously (and even immorally in many particular
instances) it pursues a utilitarian aim of general
improvement. And yet there is something esthetic
about it, since the comic comes into being just when
society and the individual, freed from the worry of
self-preservation, begin to regard themselves as works
of art. In a word, if a circle be drawn round
those actions and dispositions—implied
in individual or social life—to which their
natural consequences bring their own penalties, there
remains outside this sphere of emotion and struggle—and
within a neutral zone in which man simply exposes
himself to man’s curiosity—a certain
rigidity of body, mind and character, that society
would still like to get rid of in order to obtain
from its members the greatest possible degree of elasticity
and sociability. This rigidity is the comic,
and laughter is its corrective.
Still, we must not accept this formula as a definition
of the comic. It is suitable only for cases that
are elementary, theoretical and perfect, in which
the comic is free from all adulteration. Nor do
we offer it, either, as an explanation. We prefer
to make it, if you will, the leitmotiv which is to
accompany all our explanations. We must ever
keep it in mind, though without dwelling on it too
much, somewhat as a skilful fencer must think of the
discontinuous movements of the lesson whilst his body
is given up to the continuity of the fencing-match.
We will now endeavour to reconstruct the sequence
of comic forms, taking up again the thread that leads
from the horseplay of a clown up to the most refined
effects of comedy, following this thread in its often
unforeseen windings, halting at intervals to look
around, and finally getting back, if possible, to
the point at which the thread is dangling and where
we shall perhaps find—since the comic oscillates
between life and art—the general relation
that art bears to life.