capacity to distinguish errors from reality, nor judgment
enough to perceive that what appeared improving and
charming in theory, frequently became destructive and
improper when attempted to be put into practice.
Returned to his own country, his acquired half-learning
made him wholly dissatisfied with his Government,
with his religion, and with himself. In our Revolution
he thought that he saw the first approach towards
the perfection of the human species, and that it would
soon make mankind as good and as regenerated in society
as was promised in books. With our own regenerators
he extenuated the crimes which sullied their work
from its first page, and declared them even necessary
to make the conclusion so much the more complete.
When, therefore, Bonaparte, in 1796, entered the
capital of Lombardy, Melzi was among the first of
the Italian nobility who hailed him as a deliverer.
The numerous vexations and repeated pillage of our
Government, generals, commissaries, and soldiers,
did not abate his zeal nor alter his opinion.
“The faults and sufferings of individuals,”
he said, “are nothing to the goodness of the
cause, and do not impair the utility of the whole.”
To him, everything the Revolution produced was the
best; the murder of thousands and the ruin of millions
were, with him, nothing compared with the benefit
the universe would one day derive from the principles
and instruction of our armed and unarmed philosophers.
In recompense for so much complacency, and such great
patriotism, Bonaparte appointed him, in 1797, a plenipotentiary
from the Cisalpine Republic to the Congress at Rastadt;
and, in 1802, a vice-president of the Italian Republic.
As Melzi was a sincere and disinterested republican
fanatic, he did not much approve of the strides Bonaparte
made towards a sovereignty that annihilated the sovereignty
of his sovereign people. In a conference, however,
with Talleyrand, at Lyons, in February, 1802, he was
convinced that this age was not yet ripe for all the
improvements our philosophers intended to confer on
it; and that, to prevent it from retrogading to the
point where it was found by our Revolution, it was
necessary that it should be ruled by enlightened men,
such as he and Bonaparte, to whom he advised him by
all means never to give the least hint about liberty
and equality. Our Minister ended his fraternal
counsel with obliging Melzi to sign a stipulation
for a yearly sum, as a douceur for the place he occupied.
The sweets of power shortly caused Melzi to forget
both the tenets of his philosophy and his schemes
of regeneration. He trusted so much to the promises
of Bonaparte and Talleyrand, that he believed himself
destined to reign for life, and was, therefore, not
a little surprised when he was ordered by Napoleon
the First to descend and salute Eugene de Beauharnais
as the deputy Sovereign of the Sovereign King of Italy.
He was not philosopher enough to conceal his chagrin,
and bowed with such a bad grace to the new Viceroy
that it was visible he would have preferred seeing
in that situation an Austrian Archduke as a governor-general.
To soften his disappointment, Bonaparte offered to
make him a Prince, and with that rank indemnify him
for breaking the promises given at Lyons, where it
is known that the influence of Melzi, more than the
intrigues of Talleyrand, determined the Italian Consulta
in the choice of a president.