without the most serious detriment to the commonwealth,
pass a law for scourging him. On the other hand
the Act which allowed the affirmation of a Quaker
to be received in criminal cases allowed, and most
justly and reasonably, such affirmation to be received
in the case of a past as well as of a future misdemeanour
or felony. If we try the Act which attainted
Fenwick by these rules we shall find that almost all
the numerous writers who have condemned it have condemned
it on wrong grounds. It made no retrospective
change in the substantive law. The crime was
not new. It was high treason as defined by the
Statute of Edward the Third. The punishment was
not new. It was the punishment which had been
inflicted on traitors of ten generations. All
that was new was the procedure; and, if the new procedure
had been intrinsically better than the old procedure,
the new procedure might with perfect propriety have
been employed. But the procedure employed in
Fenwick’s case was the worst possible, and would
have been the worst possible if it had been established
from time immemorial. However clearly political
crime may have been defined by ancient laws, a man
accused of it ought not to be tried by a crowd of
five hundred and thirteen eager politicians, of whom
he can challenge none even with cause, who have no
judge to guide them, who are allowed to come in and
go out as they choose, who hear as much or as little
as they choose of the accusation and of the defence,
who are exposed, during the investigation, to every
kind of corrupting influence, who are inflamed by
all the passions which animated debates naturally
excite, who cheer one orator and cough down another,
who are roused from sleep to cry Aye or No, or who
are hurried half drunk from their suppers to divide.
For this reason, and for no other, the attainder of
Fenwick is to be condemned. It was unjust and
of evil example, not because it was a retrospective
Act, but because it was an act essentially judicial,
performed by a body destitute of all judicial qualities.
The bill for punishing Duncombe was open to all the
objections which can be urged against the bill for
punishing Fenwick, and to other objections of even
greater weight. In both cases the judicial functions
were usurped by a body unfit to exercise such functions.
But the bill against Duncombe really was, what the
bill against Fenwick was not, objectionable as a retrospective
bill. It altered the substantive criminal law.
It visited an offence with a penalty of which the
offender, at the time when he offended, had no notice.
It may be thought a strange proposition that the bill
against Duncombe was a worse bill than the bill against
Fenwick, because the bill against Fenwick struck at
life, and the bill against Duncombe struck only at
property. Yet this apparent paradox is a sober
truth. Life is indeed more precious than property.
But the power of arbitrarily taking away the lives
of men is infinitely less likely to be abused than