law and nothing else, you must look at it as a bad
man, who cares only for the material consequences
which such knowledge enables him to predict, not as
a good one, who finds his reasons for conduct, whether
inside the law or outside of it, in the vaguer sanctions
of conscience. The theoretical importance of the
distinction is no less, if you would reason on your
subject aright. The law is full of phraseology
drawn from morals, and by the mere force of language
continually invites us to pass from one domain to the
other without perceiving it, as we are sure to do
unless we have the boundary constantly before our
minds. The law talks about rights, and duties,
and malice, and intent, and negligence, and so forth,
and nothing is easier, or, I may say, more common
in legal reasoning, than to take these words in their
moral sense, at some state of the argument, and so
to drop into fallacy. For instance, when we speak
of the rights of man in a moral sense, we mean to
mark the limits of interference with individual freedom
which we think are prescribed by conscience, or by
our ideal, however reached. Yet it is certain
that many laws have been enforced in the past, and
it is likely that some are enforced now, which are
condemned by the most enlightened opinion of the time,
or which at all events pass the limit of interference,
as many consciences would draw it. Manifestly,
therefore, nothing but confusion of thought can result
from assuming that the rights of man in a moral sense
are equally rights in the sense of the Constitution
and the law. No doubt simple and extreme cases
can be put of imaginable laws which the statute-making
power would not dare to enact, even in the absence
of written constitutional prohibitions, because the
community would rise in rebellion and fight; and this
gives some plausibility to the proposition that the
law, if not a part of morality, is limited by it.
But this limit of power is not coextensive with any
system of morals. For the most part it falls
far within the lines of any such system, and in some
cases may extend beyond them, for reasons drawn from
the habits of a particular people at a particular
time. I once heard the late Professor Agassiz
say that a German population would rise if you added
two cents to the price of a glass of beer. A
statute in such a case would be empty words, not because
it was wrong, but because it could not be enforced.
No one will deny that wrong statutes can be and are
enforced, and we would not all agree as to which were
the wrong ones.
The confusion with which I am dealing besets confessedly
legal conceptions. Take the fundamental question,
What constitutes the law? You will find some
text writers telling you that it is something different
from what is decided by the courts of Massachusetts
or England, that it is a system of reason, that it
is a deduction from principles of ethics or admitted
axioms or what not, which may or may not coincide
with the decisions. But if we take the view of
our friend the bad man we shall find that he does
not care two straws for the axioms or deductions,
but that he does want to know what the Massachusetts
or English courts are likely to do in fact. I
am much of this mind. The prophecies of what
the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious,
are what I mean by the law.