to accomplish his end by a gentle diplomacy, a conciliatory
manner, which is often misunderstood by those who
surround him and who interpret gentleness of spirit
as smallness of spirit and self-restraint as weakness.
It would be truer to describe Augustus as a man who
wore most skilfully the mask of an ordinary man though
himself an extraordinary man. The more we study
the chaotic condition of Rome under the Second Triumvirate
and the more fully we realise not only the total disorganisation
of the forms of government but also the absolute demoralisation
of the individual citizen, the more we appreciate
the almost impossible task which was set for Augustus
and which he successfully accomplished. For one
hundred years (B.C. 133-31), from Tiberius Gracchus
to Actium, hardly a decade had passed which had not
brought forth some terrible revolution for Rome.
Even the great Caesar had failed, had not divined aright
the only treatment to which the disease of the age
would yield, for although the blows which actually
killed Caesar may have been merely an accident in
history, the deed of irresponsible men, his fall was
no accident but was the inevitable logical outcome
of his imperial policy. But Augustus succeeded
in establishing a form of government which enabled
himself and his connexion to occupy the throne for
almost a hundred years, and even then though revolutions
came, his constitution was the main bulwark of government
in succeeding centuries. It would take us too
far from our present subject to answer in any completeness
the question of how he succeeded, but a word or two
may be said in general, and the rest will become clearer
when we examine his reorganisation of religion.
The secret of Augustus’s success was the infinite
tact and diplomacy by which he managed to strengthen
the throne and his own position on it while apparently
restoring the form of the republic and the manners
of the old days. It is open to question whether
he was actuated by a consideration of the good of
the state, or by a regard for his own selfish ends,
but it is beyond question that he gave to Rome the
only form of government which could eradicate the
habit of revolution, and thus saved the state.
He succeeded because he did not underestimate the
difficulty of the task, and accordingly brought to
bear on it every possible influence, emphasising especially
the psychological element and being willing to go
a long way around in order to arrive at his goal.
He was not content with a mere temporary makeshift,
which might carry him to the end of his own life;
he was laying foundations for the future. Nowhere
is this more clearly stated than in one of his edicts,
where he says:—“May it fall to my
lot to establish the state firm and strong and to
obtain the wished-for fruit of my labours, that I may
be called the author of it and that when I die I may
carry with me the hope that the foundations which
I have laid may abide.” These abiding foundations
must be laid deep in the national psychology, and it