of Ennius has grown into a triple truth, and there
are no less than three distinct religions: the
religion of poets, of philosophers, and of statesmen.
The religion of the poets, by which he means the mythological
treatment of the gods, he condemns as worthless because
it tells a great many things about the gods which
are not true and which are entirely unworthy of them.
The religion of philosophers he does not consider suitable
to the state, because it contains many things which
are superfluous, and some which are injurious.
The superfluous things may be allowed to pass, but
the injurious things, by which he evidently means the
doctrines of Euhemeros, are a very serious matter,
not because they are untrue but because the knowledge
of them is inexpedient for the masses. The religion
of the statesman can have no part in these things,
even if they are true; and a man as a citizen of the
state must believe in many things, or profess belief
in them, which the same man, as an individual and
a philosopher, knows are false. Scaevola’s
honest well-intentioned effort to support the religion
of the state was naturally a failure. The very
“masses” in whose behalf Scaevola was calling
on his fellow-citizens to undergo these casuistical
gymnastics soon cared more for Bellona and Isis than
for all the gods of Numa together. But we cannot
help admiring Scaevola for his patriotism, though we
may not envy him his ethics. The state religion
could never be supported on the arguments of expediency;
every one granted its expediency, and still it fell;
its worst enemies, the politicians, granted it most
of all, and they were the only ones who put the doctrine
to any practical use. It was precisely this discovery
of its expediency and its great practical value which
caused its downfall. From the practical standpoint
the problem was settled once and for all, but as a
matter of theory it remained for the next generation,
in the person of Varro, to provide a more satisfactory
solution, and to effect something of a compromise
between the truth of philosophy and the truth of religion.
Marcus Terentius Varro came to the work equipped with
all the learning of his time and possessed of a greater
knowledge of facts than any other Roman of his or
any other day. So far as the problem of religion
was concerned, he embodied this learning in the sixteen
books of Divine Antiquities, which he very
appropriately dedicated to Julius Caesar in his capacity
as Pontifex Maximus. If Ennius’s Sacra
Historia be left out of account, his book was
the first treatise on systematic theology which Rome
ever had. In this work he desired to accomplish
three things: first, by a review of the history
of Rome to show how essential the state religion was;
second, by an examination of Greek mythology to purify
the state religion from its immoral influences; third,
to show that the state religion so purified was fully
in accord with Stoic philosophy. In regard to
the “three religions,” therefore, he agreed