of juridical discipline they add to the readiness
and sagacity of those who are called to plead or to
judge. But as human affairs and human actions
are not of a metaphysical nature, but the subject
is concrete, complex, and moral, they cannot be subjected
(without exceptions which reduce it almost to nothing)
to any certain rule. Their rules with regard to
competence were many and strict, and our lawyers have
mentioned it to their reproach. “The Civilians,”
it has been observed, “differ in nothing more
than admitting evidence; for they reject histriones,
&c., and whole tribes of people."[44] But this extreme
rigor as to competency, rejected by our law, is not
found to extend to the genus of evidence, but
only to a particular species,—personal
witnesses. Indeed, after all their efforts to
fix these things by positive and inflexible maxims,
the best Roman lawyers, in their best ages, were obliged
to confess that every case of evidence rather formed
its own rule than that any rule could be adapted to
every case. The best opinions, however, seem
to have reduced the admissibility of witnesses to
a few heads. “For if,” said Callistratus,
in a passage preserved to us in the Digest, “the
testimony is free from suspicion, either on account
of the quality of the person, namely, that he
is in a reputable situation, or for cause,
that is to say, that the testimony given is not for
reward nor favor nor for enmity, such a witness is
admissible.” This first description goes
to competence, between which and credit
Lord Hardwicke justly says the discrimination is very
nice. The other part of the text shows their
anxiety to reduce credibility itself to a fixed rule.
It proceeds, therefore,—“His Sacred
Majesty, Hadrian, issued a rescript to Vivius Varus,
Lieutenant of Cilicia, to this effect, that he who
sits in judgment is the most capable of determining
what credit is to be given to witnesses.”
The words of the letter of rescript are as follow:—“You
ought best to know what credit is to be given to witnesses,—who,
and of what dignity, and of what estimation they are,—whether
they seem to deliver their evidence with simplicity
and candor, whether they seem to bring a formed and
premeditated discourse, or whether on the spot they
give probable matter in answer to the questions that
are put to them.” And there remains a rescript
of the same prince to Valerius Verus, on the bringing
out the credit of witnesses. This appears to
go more to the general principles of evidence.
It is in these words:—“What evidence,
and in what measure or degree, shall amount to proof
in each case can be defined in no manner whatsoever
that is sufficiently certain. For, though not
always, yet frequently, the truth of the affair may
appear without any matter of public record. In
some cases the number of the witnesses, in others
their dignity and authority, is to be weighed; in others,
concurring public fame tends to confirm the credit
of the evidence in question. This alone I am
able, and in a few words, to give you as my determination:
that you ought not too readily to bind yourself to
try the cause upon any one description of evidence;
but you are to estimate by your own discretion what
you ought to credit, or what appears to you not to
be established by proof sufficient."[45]