Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Obj. 2:  Further Augustine says (Gen. ad lit. xi, 5):  “We must not suppose that the tempter would have overcome man, unless first of all there had arisen in man’s soul a movement of vainglory which should have been checked.”  Now the vainglory which preceded man’s defeat, which was accomplished through his falling into mortal sin, could be nothing more than a venial sin.  In like manner, Augustine says (Gen. ad lit. xi, 5) that “man was allured by a certain desire of making the experiment, when he saw that the woman did not die when she had taken the forbidden fruit.”  Again there seems to have been a certain movement of unbelief in Eve, since she doubted what the Lord had said, as appears from her saying (Gen. 3:3):  “Lest perhaps we die.”  Now these apparently were venial sins.  Therefore man could commit a venial sin before he committed a mortal sin.

Obj. 3:  Further, mortal sin is more opposed to the integrity of the original state, than venial sin is.  Now man could sin mortally notwithstanding the integrity of the original state.  Therefore he could also sin venially.

On the contrary, Every sin deserves some punishment.  But nothing penal was possible in the state of innocence, as Augustine declares (De Civ.  Dei xiv, 10).  Therefore he could not commit a sin that would not deprive him of that state of integrity.  But venial sin does not change man’s state.  Therefore he could not sin venially.

I answer that, It is generally admitted that man could not commit a venial sin in the state of innocence.  This, however, is not to be understood as though on account of the perfection of his state, the sin which is venial for us would have been mortal for him, if he had committed it.  Because the dignity of a person is circumstance that aggravates a sin, but it does not transfer it to another species, unless there be an additional deformity by reason of disobedience, or vow or the like, which does not apply to the question in point.  Consequently what is venial in itself could not be changed into mortal by reason of the excellence of the original state.  We must therefore understand this to mean that he could not sin venially, because it was impossible for him to commit a sin which was venial in itself, before losing the integrity of the original state by sinning mortally.

The reason for this is because venial sin occurs in us, either through the imperfection of the act, as in the case of sudden movements, in a genus of mortal sin or through some inordinateness in respect of things referred to the end, the due order of the end being safeguarded.  Now each of these happens on account of some defect of order, by reason of the lower powers not being checked by the higher.  Because the sudden rising of a movement of the sensuality in us is due to the sensuality not being perfectly subject to reason:  and the sudden rising of a movement of reason itself is due, in us, to the fact that the

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.