Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Obj. 3:  Further, if sin causes a stain, this stain is either something positive, or a pure privation.  If it be something positive, it can only be either a disposition or a habit:  for it seems that nothing else can be caused by an act.  But it is neither disposition nor habit:  for it happens that a stain remains even after the removal of a disposition or habit; for instance, in a man who after committing a mortal sin of prodigality, is so changed as to fall into a sin of the opposite vice.  Therefore the stain does not denote anything positive in the soul.  Again, neither is it a pure privation.  Because all sins agree on the part of aversion and privation of grace:  and so it would follow that there is but one stain caused by all sins.  Therefore the stain is not the effect of sin.

On the contrary, It was said to Solomon (Ecclus. 47:22):  “Thou hast stained thy glory”:  and it is written (Eph. 5:27):  “That He might present it to Himself a glorious church not having spot or wrinkle”:  and in each case it is question of the stain of sin.  Therefore a stain is the effect of sin.

I answer that, A stain is properly ascribed to corporeal things, when a comely body loses its comeliness through contact with another body, e.g. a garment, gold or silver, or the like.  Accordingly a stain is ascribed to spiritual things in like manner.  Now man’s soul has a twofold comeliness; one from the refulgence of the natural light of reason, whereby he is directed in his actions; the other, from the refulgence of the Divine light, viz. of wisdom and grace, whereby man is also perfected for the purpose of doing good and fitting actions.  Now, when the soul cleaves to things by love, there is a kind of contact in the soul:  and when man sins, he cleaves to certain things, against the light of reason and of the Divine law, as shown above (Q. 71, A. 6).  Wherefore the loss of comeliness occasioned by this contact, is metaphorically called a stain on the soul.

Reply Obj. 1:  The soul is not defiled by inferior things, by their own power, as though they acted on the soul:  on the contrary, the soul, by its own action, defiles itself, through cleaving to them inordinately, against the light of reason and of the Divine law.

Reply Obj. 2:  The action of the intellect is accomplished by the intelligible thing being in the intellect, according to the mode of the intellect, so that the intellect is not defiled, but perfected, by them.  On the other hand, the act of the will consists in a movement towards things themselves, so that love attaches the soul to the thing loved.  Thus it is that the soul is stained, when it cleaves inordinately, according to Osee 9:10:  “They . . . became abominable as those things were which they loved.”

Reply Obj. 3:  The stain is neither something positive in the soul, nor does it denote a pure privation:  it denotes a privation of the soul’s brightness in relation to its cause, which is sin; wherefore diverse sins occasion diverse stains.  It is like a shadow, which is the privation of light through the interposition of a body, and which varies according to the diversity of the interposed bodies. ________________________

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.