Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Obj. 2:  Further, the reason is a power of apprehension.  But moral virtue does not observe a mean between apprehensions, but rather a mean between operations or passions.  Therefore the mean of moral virtue is not the rational, but the real mean.

Obj. 3:  Further, a mean that is observed according to arithmetical or geometrical proportion is a real mean.  Now such is the mean of justice, as stated in Ethic. v, 3.  Therefore the mean of moral virtue is not the rational, but the real mean.

On the contrary, The Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 6) that “moral virtue observes the mean fixed, in our regard, by reason.”

I answer that, The rational mean can be understood in two ways.  First, according as the mean is observed in the act itself of reason, as though the very act of reason were made to observe the mean:  in this sense, since moral virtue perfects not the act of reason, but the act of the appetitive power, the mean of moral virtue is not the rational mean.  Secondly, the mean of reason may be considered as that which the reason puts into some particular matter.  In this sense every mean of moral virtue is a rational mean, since, as above stated (A. 1), moral virtue is said to observe the mean, through conformity with right reason.

But it happens sometimes that the rational mean is also the real mean:  in which case the mean of moral virtue is the real mean, for instance, in justice.  On the other hand, sometimes the rational mean is not the real mean, but is considered in relation to us:  and such is the mean in all the other moral virtues.  The reason for this is that justice is about operations, which deal with external things, wherein the right has to be established simply and absolutely, as stated above (Q. 60, A. 2):  wherefore the rational mean in justice is the same as the real mean, in so far, to wit as justice gives to each one his due, neither more nor less.  But the other moral virtues deal with interior passions wherein the right cannot be established in the same way, since men are variously situated in relation to their passions; hence the rectitude of reason has to be established in the passions, with due regard to us, who are moved in respect of the passions.

This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.  For the first two arguments take the rational mean as being in the very act of reason, while the third argues from the mean of justice. ________________________

THIRD ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 64, Art. 3]

Whether the Intellectual Virtues Observe the Mean?

Objection 1:  It would seem that the intellectual virtues do not observe the mean.  Because moral virtue observes the mean by conforming to the rule of reason.  But the intellectual virtues are in reason itself, so that they seem to have no higher rule.  Therefore the intellectual virtues do not observe the mean.

Obj. 2:  Further, the mean of moral virtue is fixed by an intellectual virtue:  for it is stated in Ethic. ii, 6, that “virtue observes the mean appointed by reason, as a prudent man would appoint it.”  If therefore intellectual virtue also observe the mean, this mean will have to be appointed for them by another virtue, so that there would be an indefinite series of virtues.

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.