Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

I answer that, On this question the opinion of the Stoics differed from that of the Peripatetics:  for the Stoics held that all passions are evil, while the Peripatetics maintained that moderate passions are good.  This difference, although it appears great in words, is nevertheless, in reality, none at all, or but little, if we consider the intent of either school.  For the Stoics did not discern between sense and intellect; and consequently neither between the intellectual and sensitive appetite.  Hence they did not discriminate the passions of the soul from the movements of the will, in so far as the passions of the soul are in the sensitive appetite, while the simple movements of the will are in the intellectual appetite:  but every rational movement of the appetitive part they call will, while they called passion, a movement that exceeds the limits of reason.  Wherefore Cicero, following their opinion (De Tusc.  Quaest. iii, 4) calls all passions “diseases of the soul”:  whence he argues that “those who are diseased are unsound; and those who are unsound are wanting in sense.”  Hence we speak of those who are wanting in sense of being “unsound.”

On the other hand, the Peripatetics give the name of “passions” to all the movements of the sensitive appetite.  Wherefore they esteem them good, when they are controlled by reason; and evil when they are not controlled by reason.  Hence it is evident that Cicero was wrong in disapproving (De Tusc.  Quaest. iii, 4) of the Peripatetic theory of a mean in the passions, when he says that “every evil, though moderate, should be shunned; for, just as a body, though it be moderately ailing, is not sound; so, this mean in the diseases or passions of the soul, is not sound.”  For passions are not called “diseases” or “disturbances” of the soul, save when they are not controlled by reason.

Hence the reply to the First Objection is evident.

Reply Obj. 2:  In every passion there is an increase or decrease in the natural movement of the heart, according as the heart is moved more or less intensely by contraction and dilatation; and hence it derives the character of passion.  But there is no need for passion to deviate always from the order of natural reason.

Reply Obj. 3:  The passions of the soul, in so far as they are contrary to the order of reason, incline us to sin:  but in so far as they are controlled by reason, they pertain to virtue. ________________________

THIRD ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 24, Art. 3]

Whether Passion Increases or Decreases the Goodness or Malice of an
Act?

Objection 1:  It would seem that every passion decreases the goodness of a moral action.  For anything that hinders the judgment of reason, on which depends the goodness of a moral act, consequently decreases the goodness of the moral act.  But every passion hinders the judgment of reason:  for Sallust says (Catilin.):  “All those that take counsel about matters of doubt, should be free from hatred, anger, friendship and pity.”  Therefore passion decreases the goodness of a moral act.

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.