Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

I answer that, It sometimes happens that an action is indifferent in its species, but considered in the individual it is good or evil.  And the reason of this is because a moral action, as stated above (A. 3), derives its goodness not only from its object, whence it takes its species; but also from the circumstances, which are its accidents, as it were; just as something belongs to a man by reason of his individual accidents, which does not belong to him by reason of his species.  And every individual action must needs have some circumstance that makes it good or bad, at least in respect of the intention of the end.  For since it belongs to the reason to direct; if an action that proceeds from deliberate reason be not directed to the due end, it is, by that fact alone, repugnant to reason, and has the character of evil.  But if it be directed to a due end, it is in accord with reason; wherefore it has the character of good.  Now it must needs be either directed or not directed to a due end.  Consequently every human action that proceeds from deliberate reason, if it be considered in the individual, must be good or bad.

If, however, it does not proceed from deliberate reason, but from some act of the imagination, as when a man strokes his beard, or moves his hand or foot; such an action, properly speaking, is not moral or human; since this depends on the reason.  Hence it will be indifferent, as standing apart from the genus of moral actions.

Reply Obj. 1:  For an action to be indifferent in its species can be understood in several ways.  First in such a way that its species demands that it remain indifferent; and the objection proceeds along this line.  But no action can be specifically indifferent thus:  since no object of human action is such that it cannot be directed to good or evil, either through its end or through a circumstance.  Secondly, specific indifference of an action may be due to the fact that as far as its species is concerned, it is neither good nor bad.  Wherefore it can be made good or bad by something else.  Thus man, as far as his species is concerned, is neither white nor black; nor is it a condition of his species that he should not be black or white; but blackness or whiteness is superadded to man by other principles than those of his species.

Reply Obj. 2:  The Philosopher states that a man is evil, properly speaking, if he be hurtful to others.  And accordingly, he says that the prodigal is not evil, because he hurts none save himself.  And the same applies to all others who are not hurtful to other men.  But we say here that evil, in general, is all that is repugnant to right reason.  And in this sense every individual action is either good or bad, as stated above.

Reply Obj. 3:  Whenever an end is intended by deliberate reason, it belongs either to the good of some virtue, or to the evil of some vice.  Thus, if a man’s action is directed to the support or repose of his body, it is also directed to the good of virtue, provided he direct his body itself to the good of virtue.  The same clearly applies to other actions. ________________________

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.