This answer he shows to be unavoidable, and so evidently
unavoidable that we might perhaps have been absolved
from asking the question; for, as he says, the so-called
definitions of “good”—that it
is pleasure, the desired, and so forth—are
not definitions of the predicate “good,”
but designations of the things to which this predicate
is applied by different persons. Pleasure, and
its rivals, are not synonyms for the abstract quality
“good,” but names for classes of concrete
facts that are supposed to possess that quality.
From this correct, if somewhat trifling, observation,
however, Mr. Russell, like Mr. Moore before him, evokes
a portentous dogma. Not being able to define good,
he hypostasises it. “Good and bad,”
he says, “are qualities which belong to objects
independently of our opinions, just as much as round
and square do; and when two people differ as to whether
a thing is good, only one of them can be right, though
it may be very hard to know which is right.”
“We cannot maintain that for me a thing ought
to exist on its own account, while for you it ought
not; that would merely mean that one of us is mistaken,
since in fact everything either ought to exist, or
ought not.” Thus we are asked to believe
that good attaches to things for no reason or cause,
and according to no principles of distribution; that
it must be found there by a sort of receptive exploration
in each separate case; in other words, that it is
an absolute, not a relative thing, a primary and not
a secondary quality.
That the quality “good” is indefinable
is one assertion, and obvious; but that the presence
of this quality is unconditioned is another, and astonishing.
My logic, I am well aware, is not very accurate or
subtle; and I wish Mr. Russell had not left it to me
to discover the connection between these two propositions.
Green is an indefinable predicate, and the specific
quality of it can be given only in intuition; but
it is a quality that things acquire under certain
conditions, so much so that the same bit of grass,
at the same moment, may have it from one point of
view and not from another. Right and left are
indefinable; the difference could not be explained
without being invoked in the explanation; yet everything
that is to the right is not to the right on no condition,
but obviously on the condition that some one is looking
in a certain direction; and if some one else at the
same time is looking in the opposite direction, what
is truly to the right will be truly to the left also.
If Mr. Russell thinks this is a contradiction, I understand
why the universe does not please him. The contradiction
would be real, undoubtedly, if we suggested that the
idea of good was at any time or in any relation the
idea of evil, or the intuition of right that of left,
or the quality of green that of yellow; these disembodied
essences are fixed by the intent that selects them,
and in that ideal realm they can never have any relations
except the dialectical ones implied in their nature,