of things and with such intimacy of knowledge, feels
that these things are not far from it, but dwell literally
in its heart. The revelation and the sentiment
of them, if it be thorough, is just what the things
are. The total aspects to be discerned in a body
are that body; and the movement of those aspects,
when you enact it,
is the spirit of that body,
and at the same time a part of your own spirit.
To suppose that a man’s consciousness (either
one’s own or other people’s) is a separate
fact over and above the shuffling of the things he
feels, or that these things are anything over and
above the feeling of them which exists more or less
everywhere in diffusion—that, for the mystic,
is to be once for all hopelessly intellectual, dualistic,
and diabolical. If you cannot shed the husk of
those dead categories—space, matter, mind,
truth, person—life is shut out of your heart.
And the mystic, who always speaks out of experience,
is certainly right in this, that a certain sort of
life is shut out by reason, the sort that reason calls
dreaming or madness; but he forgets that reason too
is a kind of life, and that of all the kinds—mystical,
passionate, practical, aesthetic, intellectual—with
their various degrees of light and heat, the life
of reason is that which some people may prefer.
I confess I am one of these, and I am not inclined,
even if I were able, to reproduce M. Bergson’s
sentiments as he feels them. He is his own perfect
expositor. All a critic can aim at is to understand
these sentiments as existing facts, and to give them
the place that belongs to them in the moral world.
To understand, in most cases, is intimacy enough.
Herbert Spencer says somewhere that the yolk of an
egg is homogeneous, the highly heterogeneous bird
being differentiated in it by the law of evolution.
I cannot think what assured Spencer of this homogeneity
in the egg, except the fact that perhaps it all tasted
alike, which might seem good proof to a pure empiricist.
Leibnitz, on the contrary, maintained that the organisation
of nature was infinitely deep, every part consisting
of an endless number of discrete elements. Here
we may observe the difference between good philosophy
and bad. The idea of Leibnitz is speculative
and far outruns the evidence, but it is speculative
in a well-advised, penetrating, humble, and noble fashion;
while the idea of Spencer is foolishly dogmatic, it
is a piece of ignorant self-sufficiency, like that
insular empiricism that would deny that Chinamen were
real until it had actually seen them. Nature
is richer than experience and wider than divination;
and it is far rasher and more arrogant to declare
that any part of nature is simple than to suggest
the sort of complexity that perhaps it might have.
M. Bergson, however, is on the side of Spencer.
After studiously examining the egg on every side—for
he would do more than taste it—and considering
the source and destiny of it, he would summon his