rather than in specific facts and arguments. The
first merit of classics is that “they are languages;
not particular sciences, nor definite branches of
knowledge, but literatures”. Under this
head we have such glowing sentences as these:
“Think of the many elements of thought a boy
comes in contact with when he reads Caesar and Tacitus
in succession, Herodotus and Homer, Thucydides and
Aristotle”. “See what is implied in
having read Homer intelligently through, or Thucydides
or Demosthenes; what light will have been shed on
the essence and laws of human existence, on political
society, on the relations of man to man, on human
nature itself.” There are various conceivable
ways of counter-arguing these assertions, but the
shortest is to call for the facts—the results
upon the many thousands that have passed through their
ten years of classical drill. Professor Campbell
of St. Andrews, once remarked, with reference to the
value of Greek in particular, that the question would
have to be ultimately decided by the inner consciousness
of those that have undergone the study. To this
we are entitled to add, their powers as manifested
to the world, of which powers spectators can be the
judges. When, with a few brilliant exceptions,
we discover nothing at all remarkable in the men that
have been subjected to the classical training, we
may consider it as almost a waste of time to analyse
the grandiloquent assertions of Mr. Bonamy Price.
But if we were to analyse them, we should find that
boys never read Caesar and Tacitus through
in succession; still less Thucydides Demosthenes,
and Aristotle; that very few
men read and understand
these writers; that the shortest way to come into contact
with Aristotle is to avoid his Greek altogether, and
take his expositors and translators in the modern
languages.
The professor is not insensible to the reproach that
the vaunted classical education has been a failure,
as compared with these splendid promises. He
says, however, that though many have failed to become
classical scholars in the full sense of the word, “it
does not follow that they have gained nothing from
their study of Greek and Latin; just the contrary
is the truth”. The “contrary”
must mean that they have gained something; which something
is stated to be “the extent to which the faculties
of the boy have been developed, the quantity of impalpable
but not less real attainments he has achieved, and
his general readiness for life, and for action as
a man”. But it is becoming more and more
difficult to induce people to spend a long course of
youthful years upon a confessedly impalpable
result. We might give up a few months to a speculative
and doubtful good, but we need palpable consequences
to show for our years spent on classics. Next
comes the admission that the teaching is often bad.
But why should the teaching be so bad, and what is
the hope of making it better? Then we are told
that science by itself leaves the largest and most
important portion of the youths’ nature absolutely
undeveloped. But, in the first place, it is not
proposed to reduce the school and college curriculum
to science alone; and, in the next place, who can
say what are the “impalpable” results of
science?