arising as Zeller suggests (Plat. Stud.) out of
a confusion of the visit of Epimenides and Diotima
(Symp.),—he describes as coming to Athens,
not after the attempt of Cylon, but ten years before
the Persian war. The Cretan and Lacedaemonian
hardly contribute at all to the argument of which
the Athenian is the expounder; they only supply information
when asked about the institutions of their respective
countries. A kind of simplicity or stupidity is
ascribed to them. At first, they are dissatisfied
with the free criticisms which the Athenian passes
upon the laws of Minos and Lycurgus, but they acquiesce
in his greater experience and knowledge of the world.
They admit that there can be no objection to the enquiry;
for in the spirit of the legislator himself, they
are discussing his laws when there are no young men
present to listen. They are unwilling to allow
that the Spartan and Cretan lawgivers can have been
mistaken in honouring courage as the first part of
virtue, and are puzzled at hearing for the first time
that ’Goods are only evil to the evil.’
Several times they are on the point of quarrelling,
and by an effort learn to restrain their natural feeling
(compare Shakespeare, Henry V, act iii. sc. 2).
In Book vii., the Lacedaemonian expresses a momentary
irritation at the accusation which the Athenian brings
against the Spartan institutions, of encouraging licentiousness
in their women, but he is reminded by the Cretan that
the permission to criticize them freely has been given,
and cannot be retracted. His only criterion of
truth is the authority of the Spartan lawgiver; he
is ‘interested,’ in the novel speculations
of the Athenian, but inclines to prefer the ordinances
of Lycurgus.
The three interlocutors all of them speak in the character
of old men, which forms a pleasant bond of union between
them. They have the feelings of old age about
youth, about the state, about human things in general.
Nothing in life seems to be of much importance to them;
they are spectators rather than actors, and men in
general appear to the Athenian speaker to be the playthings
of the Gods and of circumstances. Still they
have a fatherly care of the young, and are deeply impressed
by sentiments of religion. They would give confidence
to the aged by an increasing use of wine, which, as
they get older, is to unloose their tongues and make
them sing. The prospect of the existence of the
soul after death is constantly present to them; though
they can hardly be said to have the cheerful hope
and resignation which animates Socrates in the Phaedo
or Cephalus in the Republic. Plato appears to
be expressing his own feelings in remarks of this
sort. For at the time of writing the first book
of the Laws he was at least seventy-four years of
age, if we suppose him to allude to the victory of
the Syracusans under Dionysius the Younger over the
Locrians, which occurred in the year 356. Such
a sadness was the natural effect of declining years
and failing powers, which make men ask, ‘After