by them just as freely as the fireman climbs his ladder,
or as life-belts are distributed by the boatmen in
their work of rescue. And if human life were
nothing but a chronic conflagration or shipwreck, in
which all alike were fighting for bare existence,
all alike being menaced by some terrible and instant
death, this argument of the socialists might doubtless
have some truth in it. The men of exceptional
ability, by a variety of ingenious devices, might
seek to save others no less assiduously than themselves,
without expecting anything like exceptional wealth
as a reward; for there would, in a case like this,
be no question of wealth for anybody. But as
soon as the stress of such a situation was relaxed,
and the abilities of the ablest, liberated from the
task of contending with death, were left free to devote
themselves to the superfluous decoration of life,
the artificial tension of the moral motives would
be relaxed. The swimmer who had plunged into the
sea to save a woman from drowning would not take a
second plunge to rescue her silk petticoat. The
socialists, in short, when dealing with military and
other cognate heroisms, ignore both of the causes which
alone make such heroisms possible. They ignore
the fact that the internal motive is essentially isolated
and exceptional. They ignore the further fact
that the circumstances which alone give this motive
play are essentially exceptional also, and could never
be reproduced in social life at large, except at the
cost of making all human life intolerable.
I have called special attention to this particular
socialistic argument, partly because socialists, and
other sentimental thinkers, like Ruskin, attach such
extreme importance to it; but mainly because it affords
us an exceptionally striking illustration of the manner
in which they are accustomed to reason about matters
with regard to which they ostentatiously profess themselves
to be the pioneers of accurate science. One of
the principal grounds—to repeat what has
been said already—on which they attack
what they call the Economics of Capitalism, is that
it deals exclusively with the actions of “the
economic man,” or the man whose one motive is
the appropriation of wealth. Such a man, they
say, is an abstraction. He does not exist in
reality; and if economics is to have any scientific
value it must deal with man as a whole, in all his
living complexity. As applied to the orthodox
economists this criticism has an element of truth in
it; but when the socialists attempt to act on their
own loudly boasted principles, and deal with human
nature as a whole instead of only one of its elements,
they do nothing but travesty the error which they set
out with denouncing. The one-motived economic
man who cares only for personal gain is, no doubt,
an abstraction, like the lines and points of Euclid.
Still the motive ascribed to him is one which has a
real existence and produces real effects. It
has been defined with accuracy; and by studying its