of socialism as understood and accepted by the intelligent
disciples, and not the worn-out and discredited theories
of Marx.” Another was good enough to tell
me that I had “cleverly accomplished the task
of exposing the errors of Marx, both of premise and
of logic”; but the leaders of socialistic thought
“in its later developments” had, he proceeded
to say, long ago outgrown these. A third wrote
me a letter bristling with all kinds of challenges,
and asked me if I thought, for example, that socialists
were such fools as not to recognise that the talents
of an inventor like Mr. Edison increased the productivity
of labour by the new direction which they gave to
it. I might multiply similar quotations, but one
more will be enough here. It is taken from a
long article directed against myself by Mr. Hillquit—a
writer to whom my special attention was called as by
far the most accomplished exponent, among the militant
socialists of America, of socialism in its most logical
and most highly developed form. “It requires,”
said Mr. Hillquit, “no special genius to demonstrate
that all labour is not alike, nor equally productive.
It is still more obvious that common manual labour
is impotent to produce the wealth of modern nations—that
organisation, direction, and control are essential
to productive work in the field of modern production,
and are just as much a factor in it as mere physical
effort."[3]
But we need not confine ourselves to my own late critics
in America. The general history of socialism
as a reasoned theory is practically the same in one
country as in another. The intellectual socialists
in England, among whom Mr. Bernard Shaw and Mr. Sidney
Webb are prominent, express themselves in even plainer
terms with regard to the part which directive ability,
as opposed to labour, plays in the modern world.
“Ability,” says Mr. Shaw, employing the
very word, is often the factor which determines whether
a given industry shall make a loss of five per cent.
or else a profit of twenty; and Mr. Webb, as we shall
have occasion to see presently, carries the argument
further, and states it in greater detail.
Why, then, it may be asked, should a critic of contemporary
socialism think it worth while to expose with so much
minuteness a fallacy which intellectual socialists
now all agree in repudiating, and to insist with such
emphasis on facts which they profess to recognise as
self-evident? To this question there are two
answers.
One of these I indicated at the close of our opening
chapter; and this at the cost of what in logic is
a mere digression, it will be desirable, for practical
purposes, to state it with greater fulness.