has reverted to the Italian inspiration. The
influence of Canova and the example of Pradier and
Etex were not lasting. Indeed, Greek sculpture
has perished so completely that it sometimes seems
to live only in its legend. With the modern French
school, the academic school, it is quite supplanted
by the sculpture of the Renaissance. And this
is not unreasonable. The Renaissance sculpture
is modern; its masters did finely and perfectly what
since their time has been done imperfectly, but essentially
its artistic spirit is the modern artistic spirit,
full of personality, full of expression, careless
of the type. Nowadays we patronize a little the
ideal. You may hear very intelligent critics in
Paris—who in Paris is not an intelligent
critic?—speak disparagingly of the Greek
want of expression; of the lack of passion, of vivid
interest, of significance in a word, in Greek sculpture
of the Periclean epoch. The conception of absolute
beauty having been discovered to be an abstraction,
the tradition of the purely ideal has gone with it.
The caryatids of the Erechtheum, the horsemen of the
Parthenon frieze, the reliefs of the Nike Apteros
balustrade are admired certainly; but they are hardly
sympathetically admired; there is a tendency to relegate
them to the limbo of subjects for aesthetic lectures.
And yet no one can have carefully examined the brilliant
productions of modern French sculpture without being
struck by this apparent paradox: that, whereas
all its canons are drawn from a study of the Renaissance,
its chief characteristic is, at bottom, a lack of
expression, a carefulness for the type. The explanation
is this: in the course of time, which “at
last makes all things even,” the individuality,
the romanticism of the Renaissance has itself become
the type, is now itself become “classical,”
and the modern attitude toward it, however sympathetic
compared with the modern attitude toward the antique,
is to a noteworthy degree factitious and artificial.
And in art everything depends upon the attitude of
mind. It is this which prevents Ingres from being
truly Raphaelesque, and Pradier from being really
classical. If, therefore, it can justly be said
of modern French sculpture that its sympathy for the
Renaissance sculpture obscures its vision of the ideal,
it is clearly to be charged with the same absence
of individual significance with which its thick-and-thin
partisans reproach the antique. The circumstance
that, like the Renaissance sculpture, it deals far
more largely in pictorial expression than the antique
does, is, if it deals in them after the Renaissance
fashion and not after a fashion of its own, quite
beside the essential fact. There is really nothing
in common between an academic French sculptor of the
present day and an Italian sculptor of the fifteenth
century, except the possession of what is called the
modern spirit. But the modern spirit manifests
itself in an enormous gamut, and the differences of
its manifestations are as great in their way, and
so far as our interest in them is concerned, as the
difference between their inspiration and the mediaeval
or the antique inspiration.