great doctrine of verification. They apply it
rigorously to one set of facts, and then utterly fail
to see that it is equally applicable to another.
They apply it to religion, and declare that the dogmas
of religion are dreams; but when they pass from the
dogmas of religion to those of morality, they not
only do not use their test, but unconsciously they
denounce it with the utmost vehemence. Thus Mr.
Leslie Stephen, in the very essay from which I have
just now quoted, not only has recourse, for giving
weight to his arguments, to such ethical epithets
as low, lofty, and even sacred,
but he puts forward as his own motive for speaking,
a belief which on his own showing is a dream.
That motive, he says, is devotion to truth for its
own sake—the only principle that is really
worthy of man. His argument is simply this.
It is man’s holiest and most important duty
to discover the truth at all costs, and the one test
of truth is physical verification. Here he tells
us we find the only high morality, and the men who
cling to religious dream-dogmas which they cannot
physically verify, can only answer their opponents,
says Mr. Stephen, ‘by a shriek or a sneer.’
‘The sentiment,’ he proceeds, ’which
the dreamer most thoroughly hates and misunderstands,
is the love of truth for its own sake. He cannot
conceive why a man should attack a lie simply because
it is a lie.’ Mr. Stephen is wrong.
That is exactly what the dreamer can do, and no one
else but he; and Mr. Stephen is himself a dreamer
when he writes and feels like this. Why, let me
ask him, should the truth be loved? Do the ‘perceptions,’
which are for him the only valid guides, tell him
so? The perceptions tell him, as he expressly
says, that the truths of nature, so far as man is concerned
with them, are ‘harsh’ truths.
Why should ‘harsh’ things be loveable?
Or supposing Mr. Stephen does love them, why is that
love ‘lofty’? and why should he
so brusquely command all other men to share it? Low
and lofty—what has Mr. Stephen to
do with words like these? They are part of the
language of dreamland, not of real life. Mr. Stephen
has no right to them. If he has, he must be able
to draw a hard and fast line between them; for if
his conceptions of them be ‘vague in outline’
and ‘unsubstantial,’ they belong
by his own express definition to the land of dreams.
But this is what Mr. Stephen, with the solemn imbecility
of his school, is quite incapable of seeing.
Professor Huxley is in exactly the same case.
He says, as we have seen already, that, come what may
of it, our highest morality is to follow truth; that
the ’lowest depth of immorality’
is to pretend to believe what we see no reason for
believing;’ and that our only proper reasons
for belief are some physical, some perceptible
evidence. And yet at the same time he says that
to ‘attempt to upset morality’ by
the help of the physical sciences is about as rational