exactly with some points on the plan or section, these
are really of no more importance than other points
which might just as well have been taken. The
theorist draws our attention to those points in the
building which correspond with his geometry, and leaves
on one side those which do not. Now it may certainly
be assumed that any builders intending to lay out
a building on the basis of a geometrical figure would
have done so with precise exactitude, and that they
would have selected the most obviously important points
of the plan or section for the geometrical spacing.
In illustration of this point, I have given (Fig. 25)
a skeleton diagram of a Roman arch, supposed to be
set out on a geometrical figure. The center of
the circle is on the intersection of lines connecting
the outer projection of the main cornice with the
perpendiculars from those points on the ground line.
This point at the intersection is also the center
of the circle of the archway itself. But the
upper part of the imaginary circle beyond cuts the
middle of the attic cornice. If the arch were
to be regarded as set out in reference to this circle,
it should certainly have given the most important
line—the top line, of the upper cornice,
not an inferior and less important line; and that
is pretty much the case with all these proportion
theories (except in regard to Greek Doric temples);
they are right as to one or two points of the building,
but break down when you attempt to apply them further.
It is exceedingly probable that many of these apparent
geometric coincidences really arise, quite naturally,
from the employment of some fixed measure of division
in setting out buildings. Thus, if an apartment
of somewhere about 30 feet by 25 feet is to be set
out, the builder employing a foot measure naturally
sets out exactly 30 feet one way and 25 feet the other
way. It is easier and simpler to do so than to
take chance fractional measurements. Then comes
your geometrical theorist, and observes that “the
apartment is planned precisely in the proportion of
six to five.” So it is, but it is only
the philosophy of the measuring-tape, after all.
Secondly, it is a question whether the value of this
geometrical basis is so great as has sometimes been
argued, seeing that the results of it in most cases
cannot be judged by the eye. If, for instance,
the room we are in were nearly in the proportion of
seven in length to five in width, I doubt whether
any of us here could tell by looking at it whether
it were truly so or not, or even, if it were a foot
out one way or the other, in which direction the excess
lay; and if this be the case, the advantage of such
a geometrical basis must be rather imaginary than real.
[Illustration: Figs. 26 through 28]