in equal times, which plays so important a part in
musical form, is discernible in architecture as a
rhythm in space. We may treat a cottage type of
design, no doubt, with a playful irregularity, especially
if this follows and is suggested by an irregularity,
of plan. But in architecture on a grand scale,
whether it be in a Greek colonnade or a Gothic arcade,
we cannot tolerate irregularity of spacing except where
some constructive necessity affords an obvious and
higher reason for it. Then, again, we find the
unwritten law running throughout all architecture
that a progress of line in one direction requires to
be stopped in a marked and distinct manner when it
has run its course, and we find a similarly felt necessity
in regard to musical form. The repetition so
common at the close of a piece of music of the same
chord several times in succession is exactly analogous
to the repetition of cross lines at the necking of
a Doric column to stop the vertical lines of the fluting,
or to the strongly marked horizontal lines of a cornice
which form the termination of the height or upward
progress of an architectural design. The analogy
is here very close. A less close analogy may
also be felt between an architectural and a musical
composition regarded as a whole. A fugue of Bach’s
is really a built-up structure of tones (as Browning
has so finely put it in his poem, “Abt Vogler"),
in accordance with certain ideas of relation and proportion,
just as a temple or a cathedral is a built-up structure
of lines and spaces in accordance with ideas of relation
and proportion. Both appeal to the same sense
of proportion and construction in the brain; the one
through the ear, the other through the eye. Then,
in regard to architecture again, we have further limiting
conditions arising not only out of the principle of
construction employed, but out of the physical properties
of the very material we employ. A treatment that
is suitable and expressive for a stone construction
is quite unsuitable for a timber construction.
Details which are effective and permanent in marble
are ineffective and perishable in stone, and so; on
and the outcome of all this is that all architectural
design has to be judged, not by any easy and ready
reference to exterior physical nature, with which it
has nothing to do, but by a process of logical reasoning
as to the relation of the design to the practical
conditions, first, which are its basis, and as to
the relation of the parts to each other. Of course
beyond all this there is in architecture, as in music,
something which defies analysis, which appeals to
our sense of delight we know not how or why, and probably
we do not want to know; the charm might be dissolved
if we did. But up to this point architectural
design and expression are based on reasoning from
certain premises. The design is good or bad as
it recognizes or ignores the logic of the case, and
the criticism of it must rest on a similar basis.
It is a matter of thought in both cases, and without
thought it can neither be designed nor appreciated
to any purpose, and this is the leading idea which
I wish to urge and to illustrate in these lectures.