was held suspect, and this divorce between faith and
reason was vehemently rejected by the prelates and
the doctors of that time, and condemned in the last
Lateran Council under Leo X. On that occasion also,
scholars were urged to work for the removal of the
difficulties that appeared to set theology and philosophy
at variance. The doctrine of their incompatibility
continued to hold its ground
incognito.
Pomponazzi was suspected of it, although he declared
himself otherwise; and that very sect of the Averroists
survived as a school. It is thought that Caesar
Cremoninus, [81] a philosopher famous in his time,
was one of its mainstays. Andreas Cisalpinus,
a physician (and an author of merit who came nearest
after Michael Servetus to the discovery of the circulation
of the blood), was accused by Nicolas Taurel (in a
book entitled
Alpes Caesae) of belonging to
these anti-religious Peripatetics. Traces of this
doctrine are found also in the
Circulus Pisanus
Claudii Berigardi, an author of French nationality
who migrated to Italy and taught philosophy at Pisa:
but especially the writings and the letters of Gabriel
Naude, as well as the
Naudaeana, show that
Averroism still lived on when this learned physician
was in Italy. Corpuscular philosophy, introduced
shortly after, appears to have extinguished this excessively
Peripatetic sect, or perhaps to have been intermixed
with its teaching. It may be indeed that there
have been Atomists who would be inclined to teach
dogmas like those of the Averroists, if circumstances
so permitted: but this abuse cannot harm such
good as there is in Corpuscular philosophy, which can
very well be combined with all that is sound in Plato
and in Aristotle, and bring them both into harmony
with true theology.
12. The Reformers, and especially Luther, as
I have already observed, spoke sometimes as if they
rejected philosophy, and deemed it inimical to faith.
But, properly speaking, Luther understood by philosophy
only that which is in conformity with the ordinary
course of Nature, or perhaps even philosophy as it
was taught in the schools. Thus for example he
says that it is impossible in philosophy, that is,
in the order of Nature, that the word be made flesh;
and he goes so far as to maintain that what is true
in natural philosophy might be false in ethics.
Aristotle was the object of his anger; and so far
back as the year 1516 he contemplated the purging of
philosophy, when he perhaps had as yet no thoughts
of reforming the Church. But at last he curbed
his vehemence and in the Apology for the Augsburg
Confession allowed a favourable mention of Aristotle
and his Ethics. Melanchthon, a man of
sound and moderate ideas, made little systems from
the several parts of philosophy, adapted to the truths
of revelation and useful in civic life, which deserve
to be read even now. After him, Pierre de la
Ramee entered the lists. His philosophy was much
in favour: the sect of the Ramists was powerful
in Germany, gaining many adherents among the Protestants,
and even concerning itself with theology, until the
revival of Corpuscular philosophy, which caused that
of Ramee to fall into [82] oblivion and weakened
the authority of the Peripatetics.