best, the evil or the lesser good which he rejects
will still be possible in itself. Otherwise the
necessity of good would be geometrical (so to speak)
or metaphysical, and altogether absolute; the contingency
of things would be destroyed, and there would be no
choice. But necessity of this kind, which does
not destroy the possibility of the contrary, has the
name by analogy only: it becomes effective not
through the mere essence of things, but through that
which is outside them and above them, that is, through
the will of God. This necessity is called moral,
because for the wise what is necessary and what is
owing are equivalent things; and when it is always
followed by its effect, as it indeed is in the perfectly
wise, that is, in God, one can say that it is a happy
necessity. The more nearly creatures approach
this, the closer do they come to perfect felicity.
Moreover, necessity of this kind is not the necessity
one endeavours to avoid, and which destroys morality,
reward and commendation. For that which it brings
to pass does not happen whatever one may do and whatever
one may will, but because one desires it. A will
to which it is natural to choose well deserves most
to be commended; and it carries with it its own reward,
which is supreme happiness. And as this constitution
of the divine nature gives an entire satisfaction to
him who possesses it, it is also the best and the
most desirable from the point of view of the creatures
who are all dependent upon God. If the will of
God had not as its rule the principle of the best,
it would tend towards evil, which would be worst of
all; or else it would be indifferent somehow to good
and to evil, and guided by chance. But a will
that would always drift along at random would scarcely
be any better for the government of the universe than
the fortuitous concourse of corpuscles, without the
existence of divinity. And even though God should
abandon himself to chance only in some cases, and
in a certain way (as he would if he did not always
tend entirely towards the best, and if he were capable
of preferring a lesser good to a greater good, that
is, an evil to a good, since that which [388] prevents
a greater good is an evil) he would be no less imperfect
than the object of his choice. Then he would
not deserve absolute trust; he would act without reason
in such a case, and the government of the universe
would be like certain games equally divided between
reason and luck. This all proves that this objection
which is made against the choice of the best perverts
the notions of free and necessary, and represents the
best to us actually as evil: but that is either
malicious or absurd.
&nb
sp; [389]
*
* * * *
EXCURSUS ON THEODICY
392
published by the author in Memoires de Trevoux
July 1712