empirically the 47th proposition of the first book
of Euclid. Now supposing that some of these pieces
taken from the two smaller squares are lost, something[262]
will be lacking in the large square that is to be formed
from them; and this defective combination, far from
pleasing, will be disagreeably ugly. If then
the pieces that remained, composing the faulty combination,
were taken separately without any regard to the large
square to whose formation they ought to contribute,
one would group them together quite differently to
make a tolerably good combination. But as soon
as the lost pieces are retrieved and the gap in the
faulty combination is filled, there will ensue a beautiful
and regular thing, the complete large square:
this perfect combination will be far more beautiful
than the tolerably good combination which had been
made from the pieces one had not mislaid alone.
The perfect combination corresponds to the universe
in its entirety, and the faulty combination that is
a part of the perfect one corresponds to some part
of the universe, where we find defects which the Author
of things has allowed, because otherwise, if he had
wished to re-shape this faulty part and make thereof
a tolerably good combination, the whole would not then
have been so beautiful. For the parts of the
faulty combination, grouped better to make a tolerably
good combination, could not have been used properly
to form the whole and perfect combination. Thomas
Aquinas had an inkling of these things when he said:
ad prudentem gubernatorem pertinet, negligere aliquem
defectum bonitatis in parte, ut faciat augmentum bonitatis
in toto (Thom.,
Contra Gentiles, lib. 2,
c. 71). Thomas Gatacre, in his Notes on the book
of Marcus Aurelius (lib. 5, cap. 8, with M. Bayle),
cites also passages from authors who say that the
evil of the parts is often the good of the whole.
215. Let us return to M. Bayle’s illustrations.
He imagines a prince (p. 963) who is having a city
built, and who, in bad taste, aims rather at airs
of magnificence therein, and a bold and unusual style
of architecture, than at the provision of conveniences
of all kinds for the inhabitants. But if this
prince has true magnanimity he will prefer the convenient
to the magnificent architecture. That is M. Bayle’s
judgement. I consider, however, that there are
cases where one will justifiably prefer beauty of
construction in a palace to the convenience of a few
domestics. But I admit that the construction
would be bad, however beautiful it might be, if it
were a cause of diseases to the inhabitants; provided
it was possible to make one that would be better,
taking into account beauty, convenience and health
all together. It may be, indeed, that one cannot
have all these[263] advantages at once. Thus,
supposing one wished to build on the northern and
more bracing side of the mountain, if the castle were
then bound to be of an unendurable construction, one
would prefer to make it face southward.