writer who had spoken in commendation of the work
of Chrysippus [Greek: peri dynaton] ("citatur
honorifice apud Arrianum”, Menag. in
Laert.,
I, 7, 341) for assuredly these words, “[Greek:
gegraphe de kai Chrysippos thaumastos],
etc.,
de his rebus mira scripsit Chrysippus”,
etc.,
are not in that connexion a eulogy. That is shown
by the passages immediately before and after it.
Dionysius of Halicarnassus (
De Collocat. Verbor.,
c. 17, p. m. 11) mentions two treatises by Chrysippus,
wherein, under a title that promised something different,
much of the logicians’ territory had been explored.
The work was entitled “[Greek: peri tes
syntaxeos ton tou logou meron], de partium orationis
collocatione”, and treated only of propositions
true and false, possible and impossible, contingent
and equivocal,
etc., matter that our Schoolmen
have pounded down and reduced to its essence.
Take note that Chrysippus recognized that past things
were necessarily true, which Cleanthes had not been
willing to admit. (Arrian,
ubi supra, p. m.
165.) “[Greek: Ou pan de parelelythos alethes
anankaion esti, kathaper hoi peri Kleanthen pheresthai
dokousi]. Non omne praeteritum ex necessitate
verum est, ut illi qui Cleanthem sequuntur sentiunt.”
We have already seen (p. 562, col. 2) that Abelard
is alleged to have taught a doctrine which resembles
that of Diodorus. I think that the Stoics pledged
themselves to give a wider range to possible things
than to future things, for the purpose of mitigating
the odious and frightful conclusions which were drawn
from their dogma of fatality.’
It is sufficiently evident that Cicero when writing
to Varro the words that have just been quoted (lib.
9, Ep. 4, Ad Familiar.) had not enough comprehension
of the effect of Diodorus’s opinion, since he
found it preferable. He presents tolerably well
in his book De Fato the opinions of those writers,
but it is a pity that he has not always added the reasons
which they employed. Plutarch in his treatise
on the contradictions of the Stoics and M. Bayle are
both surprised that Chrysippus was not of the same
opinion as Diodorus, since he favours fatality.
But Chrysippus and even his master Cleanthes were
on that point more reasonable than is supposed. [233]
That will be seen as we proceed. It is open to
question whether the past is more necessary than the
future. Cleanthes held the opinion that it is.
The objection is raised that it is necessary ex
hypothesi for the future to happen, as it is necessary
ex hypothesi for the past to have happened.
But there is this difference, that it is not possible
to act on the past state, that would be a contradiction;
but it is possible to produce some effect on the future.
Yet the hypothetical necessity of both is the same:
the one cannot be changed, the other will not be; and
once that is past, it will not be possible for it
to be changed either.