from every side—thoughts which Germany had
suffered to sleep among her poets and philosophers,
every one which could lend a seductive or striking
form to a conviction already made! Henceforth
German imperialism had a theory of its own. Taught
in schools and universities, it easily moulded to
itself a nation already broken-in to passive obedience
and having no loftier ideal wherewith to oppose the
official doctrine. Many persons have explained
the aberrations of German policy as due to that theory.
For my part, I see in it nothing more than a philosophy
doomed to translate into ideas what was, in its essence,
insatiable ambition and will perverted by pride.
The doctrine is an effect rather than a cause; and
should the day come when Germany, conscious of her
moral humiliation, shall say, to excuse herself, that
she had trusted herself too much to certain theories,
that an error of judgment is not a crime, it will then
be necessary to remind her that her philosophy was
simply a translation into intellectual terms of her
brutality, her appetites, and her vices. So,
too, in most cases, doctrines are the means by which
nations and individuals seek to explain what they are
and what they do. Germany, having finally become
a predatory nation, invokes Hegel as witness; just
as a Germany enamoured of moral beauty would have
declared herself faithful to Kant, just as a sentimental
Germany would have found her tutelary genius in Jacobi
or Schopenhauer. Had she leaned in any other
direction and been unable to find at home the philosophy
she needed, she would have procured it from abroad.
Thus when she wished to convince herself that predestined
races exist, she took from France, that she might
hoist him into celebrity, a writer whom we have not
read—Gobineau.
None the less is it true that perverse ambition, once
erected into theory, feels more at ease in working
itself out to the end; a part of the responsibility
will then be thrown upon logic. If the German
race is the elect, it will be the only race which
has an unconditional right to live; the others will
be tolerated races, and this toleration will be precisely
what is called “the state of peace.”
Let war come; the annihilation of the enemy will be
the end Germany has to pursue. She will not strike
at combatants only; she will massacre women, children,
old men; she will pillage and burn; the ideal will
be to destroy towns, villages, the whole population.
Such is the conclusion of the theory. Now we
come to its aim and true principle.
As long as war was no more than a means to the settlement
of a dispute between two nations, the conflict was
localized to the two armies involved. More and
more of useless violence was eliminated; innocent
populations were kept outside the quarrel. Thus
little by little a code of war was drawn up.
From the first, however, the Prussian army, organized
as it was for conquest, did not take kindly to this
law. But from the time when Prussian militarism,