“Bosh,” said the Realist, “I will
tell you what a rose is; that is to say, I will give
you a detailed account of the properties of
Rosa
setigera, not forgetting to mention the urn-shaped
calyx-tube, the five imbricated lobes, or the open
corolla of five obovate petals.” To a Cezanne
one account would appear as irrelevant as the other,
since both omit the thing that matters—what
philosophers used to call “the thing in itself,”
what now, I imagine, they call “the essential
reality.” For, after all, what is a rose?
What is a tree, a dog, a wall, a boat? What is
the particular significance of anything? Certainly
the essence of a boat is not that it conjures up visions
of argosies with purple sails, nor yet that it carries
coals to Newcastle. Imagine a boat in complete
isolation, detach it from man and his urgent activities
and fabulous history, what is it that remains, what
is that to which we still react emotionally?
What but pure form, and that which, lying behind pure
form, gives it its significance. It was for this
Cezanne felt the emotion he spent his life in expressing.
And the second characteristic of the new movement
is a passionate interest, inherited from Cezanne, in
things regarded as ends in themselves. In saying
this I am saying no more than that the painters of
the movement are consciously determined to be artists.
Peculiarity lies in the consciousness—the
consciousness with which they set themselves to eliminate
all that lies between themselves and the pure forms
of things. To be an artist, they think, suffices.
How many men of talent, and even of genius, have missed
being effective artists because they tried to be something
else?
II
SIMPLIFICATION AND DESIGN
At the risk of becoming a bore I repeat that there
is something ludicrous about hunting for characteristics
in the art of to-day or of yesterday, or of any particular
period. In art the only important distinction
is the distinction between good art and bad. That
this pot was made in Mesopotamia about 4000 B.C.,
and that picture in Paris about 1913 A.D., is of very
little consequence. Nevertheless, it is possible,
though not very profitable, to distinguish between
equally good works made at different times in different
places; and although the practice of associating art
with the age in which it was produced can be of no
service to art or artists, I am not sure that it can
be of no service whatever. For if it be true
that art is an index to the spiritual condition of
an age, the historical consideration of art cannot
fail to throw some light on the history of civilisation.
It is conceivable therefore that a comparative study
of artistic periods might lead us to modify our conception
of human development, and to revise a few of our social
and political theories. Be that as it may, this
much is sure: should anyone wish to infer from
the art it produced the civility of an age, he must
be capable of distinguishing the work of that age from
the work of all other ages. He must be familiar
with the characteristics of the movement. It
is my intention to indicate a few of the more obvious
characteristics of the contemporary movement.