but meritorious. It is incumbent on every one
to restrain the pursuit of his personal objects within
the limits consistent with the essential interests
of others. What those limits are, it is the province
of ethical science to determine; and to keep all individuals
and aggregations of individuals within them, is the
proper office of punishment and of moral blame.
If in addition to fulfilling this obligation, persons
make the good of others a direct object of disinterested
exertions, postponing or sacrificing to it even innocent
personal indulgences, they deserve gratitude and honour,
and are fit objects of moral praise. So long
as they are in no way compelled to this conduct by
any external pressure, there cannot be too much of
it; but a necessary condition is its spontaneity;
since the notion of a happiness for all, procured
by the self-sacrifice of each, if the abnegation is
really felt to be a sacrifice, is a contradiction.
Such spontaneity by no means excludes sympathetic
encouragement; but the encouragement should take the
form of making self-devotion pleasant, not that of
making everything else painful. The object should
be to stimulate services to humanity by their natural
rewards; not to render the pursuit of our own good
in any other manner impossible, by visiting it with
the reproaches of other and of our own conscience.
The proper office of those sanctions is to enforce
upon every one, the conduct necessary to give all
other persons their fair chance: conduct which
chiefly consists in not doing them harm, and not impeding
them in anything which without harming others does
good to themselves. To this must of course be
added, that when we either expressly or tacitly undertake
to do more, we are bound to keep our promise.
And inasmuch as every one, who avails himself of the
advantages of society, leads others to expect from
him all such positive good offices and disinterested
services as the moral improvement attained by mankind
has rendered customary, he deserves moral blame if,
without just cause, he disappoints that expectation.
Through this principle the domain of moral duty is
always widening. When what once was uncommon
virtue becomes common virtue, it comes to be numbered
among obligations, while a degree exceeding what has
grown common, remains simply meritorious.
M. Comte is accustomed to draw most of his ideas of
moral cultivation from the discipline of the Catholic
Church. Had he followed that guidance in the
present case, he would have been less wide of the mark.
For the distinction which we have drawn was fully recognized
by the sagacious and far-sighted men who created the
Catholic ethics. It is even one of the stock
reproaches against Catholicism, that it has two standards
of morality, and does not make obligatory on all Christians
the highest rule of Christian perfection. It has
one standard which, faithfully acted up to, suffices
for salvation, another and a higher which when realized
constitutes a saint. M. Comte, perhaps unconsciously,
for there is nothing that he would have been more
unlikely to do if he had been aware of it, has taken
a leaf out of the book of the despised Protestantism.
Like the extreme Calvinists, he requires that all
believers shall be saints, and damns then (after his
own fashion) if they are not.