of the eighteenth century have in many respects scarcely
received their due share of appreciation. Moreover,
negative results make little display. There is
not much to show for the earnest toil that has very
likely been spent in arriving at them; and a great
deal of the intellectual labour of the last century
was of this kind. Reason had been more completely
emancipated at the Reformation than it was at first
at all aware of. Men who were engaged in battling
against certain definite abuses, and certain specified
errors, scarcely discovered at first, nor indeed for
long afterwards, that they were in reality contending
also for principles which would affect for the future
the whole groundwork of religious conviction.
They were not yet in a position to see that henceforward
authority could take only a secondary place, and that
they were installing in its room either reason or
a more subtle spiritual faculty superior even to reason
in the perception of spiritual things. It was
not until near the end of the seventeenth century that
the mind began to awaken to a full perception of the
freedom it had won—a freedom far more complete
in principle than was as yet allowed in practice.
In the eighteenth century this fundamental postulate
of the Reformation became for the first time a prominent,
and, to many minds, an absorbing subject of inquiry.
For the first time it was no longer disguised from
sight by the incidental interest of its side issues.
The assertors of the supremacy of reason were at first
arrogantly, or even insolently, self-confident, as
those who were secure of carrying all before them.
Gradually, the wiser of them began to feel that their
ambition must be largely moderated, and that they must
be content with far more negative results than they
had at first imagined. The question came to be,
what is reason unable to do? What are its limits?
and how is it to be supplemented? An immensity
of learning, and of arguments good and bad, was lavished
on either side in the controversy between the deists
and the orthodox. In the end, it may perhaps be
said that two axioms were established, which may sound
in our own day like commonplaces, but which were certainly
very insufficiently realised when the controversy
began. It was seen on the one hand that reason
was free, and that on the other it was encompassed
by limitations against which it strives in vain.
The Deists lost the day. Their objections to revelation
fell through; and Christianity rose again, strengthened
rather than weakened by their attack. Yet they
had not laboured in vain, if success may be measured,
not by the gaining of an immediate purpose, but by
solid good effected, however contrary in kind to the
object proposed. So far as a man works with a
single-hearted desire to win truth, he should rejoice
if his very errors are made, in the hands of an overruling
Providence, instrumental in establishing truth.
Christianity in England had arrived in the eighteenth
century at one of those periods of revision when it