hold of him, it is interesting to mark the direction
in which he looked for social salvation. He did
not turn to our traditional institutions; to the Church
or the Throne or the House of Lords: to a military
despotism, or an established religion, or a governing
Aristocracy: certainly not to the Middle Class
with its wealth and industry—least of all
to the Populace, with its “bright powers of
sympathy.” In an age which made an idol
of individual action, and warred against all collectivism
as tyranny, he looked for salvation to the State.
But the State, if it was to fulfil its high function,
must be a State in which every man felt that he had
a place and a share, and the authority of which he
could accept without loss of self-respect. “If
ever,” Arnold said in 1866, “there comes
a more equal state of society in England, the power
of the State for repression will be a thousand times
stronger.” He was for widening the province
of the State, and strengthening its hands, and “stablishing
it on behalf of whatever great changes are needed,
just as much as on behalf of order.” And,
forasmuch as the State, in its ideal, was “the
organ of our collective best self,” our first
duty was to cultivate, each man for himself, what
in himself was best—in short, Perfection.
“We find no basis for a firm State-power in
our ordinary selves; culture suggests one to us in
our
best self.” And so we come back
to the governing idea of the book before us, that
Culture is the foe of Anarchy.
In the Third Chapter—“Barbarians,
Philistines, Populace”—he divided
English Society into three main classes, to which he
gave three well-remembered nicknames. The aristocracy
he named (not very happily, seeing that he so greatly
admired their fine manners) the Barbarians; the Middle
Class he had already named the Philistines; and to
the great mass which lies below the Middle Class he
gave the name of “Populace.” The
name of “Philistine” in its application
to the great Middle Class dates from the Lecture on
Heine delivered from the Chair of Poetry at Oxford
in 1863. And it seems to have supplied a want
in our system of nomenclature, for it struck, and
it has remained, at least as a name for a type of
mind, if not exactly as a name for a social class.
When we originally encounter the word in the Lecture[30]
on Heine, Arnold is speaking of Heine’s life-long
battle—with what? With Philistinism.
“Philistinism! We have not the expression
in English. Perhaps we have not the word, because
we have so much of the thing. At Soli, I imagine,
they did not talk of solecisms; and here, at the very
headquarters of Goliath, nobody talks of Philistinism.
The French have adopted the term epicier (grocer)
to designate the sort of being whom the Germans designate
by the term Philistine; but the French term—besides
that it casts a slur upon a respectable class, composed
of living and susceptible members, while the original
Philistines are dead and buried long ago—is