the over-sanguine speculator, alike learn by the difficulties
which rashness entails on them, the necessity of being
more cautious in their engagements. And so throughout
the life of every citizen. In the quotation so
often made
apropos of such cases—“The
burnt child dreads the fire”—we see
not only that the analogy between this social discipline
and Nature’s early discipline of infants is
universally recognised; but we also see an implied
conviction that this discipline is of the most efficient
kind. Nay indeed, this conviction is more than
implied; it is distinctly stated. Every one has
heard others confess that only by “dearly bought
experience” had they been induced to give up
some bad or foolish course of conduct formerly pursued.
Every one has heard, in the criticism passed on the
doings of this spendthrift or the other schemer, the
remark that advice was useless, and that nothing but
“bitter experience” would produce any
effect: nothing, that is, but suffering the unavoidable
consequences. And if further proof be needed
that the natural reaction is not only the most efficient
penalty, but that no humanly-devised penalty can replace
it, we have such further proof in the notorious ill-success
of our various penal systems. Out of the many
methods of criminal discipline that have been proposed
and legally enforced, none have answered the expectations
of their advocates. Artificial punishments have
failed to produce reformation; and have in many cases
increased the criminality. The only successful
reformatories are those privately-established ones
which approximate their regime to the method of Nature—which
do little more than administer the natural consequences
of criminal conduct: diminishing the criminal’s
liberty of action as much as is needful for the safety
of society, and requiring him to maintain himself while
living under this restraint. Thus we see, both
that the discipline by which the young child is taught
to regulate its movements is the discipline by which
the great mass of adults are kept in order, and more
or less improved; and that the discipline humanly-devised
for the worst adults, fails when it diverges from
this divinely-ordained discipline, and begins to succeed
on approximating to it.
* * * *
*
Have we not here, then, the guiding principle of moral
education? Must we not infer that the system
so beneficent in its effects during infancy and maturity,
will be equally beneficent throughout youth? Can
any one believe that the method which answers so well
in the first and the last divisions of life, will
not answer in the intermediate division? Is it
not manifest that as “ministers and interpreters
of Nature” it is the function of parents to
see that their children habitually experience the
true consequences of their conduct—the natural
reactions: neither warding them off, nor intensifying
them, nor putting artificial consequences in place
of them? No unprejudiced reader will hesitate
in his assent.