which he perceives that the lines he makes hide, or
coincide with, the outlines of the object. And
then by putting a sheet of paper on the other side
of the glass, it is made manifest to him that the
lines he has thus drawn represent the object as he
saw it. They not only look like it, but he perceives
that they must be like it, because he made them agree
with its outlines; and by removing the paper he can
convince himself that they do agree with its outlines.
The fact is new and striking; and serves him as an
experimental demonstration, that lines of certain
lengths, placed in certain directions on a plane,
can represent lines of other lengths, and having other
directions, in space. By gradually changing the
position of the object, he may be led to observe how
some lines shorten and disappear, while others come
into sight and lengthen. The convergence of parallel
lines, and, indeed, all the leading facts of perspective,
may, from time to time, be similarly illustrated to
him. If he has been duly accustomed to self-help,
he will gladly, when it is suggested, attempt to draw
one of these outlines on paper, by the eye only; and
it may soon be made an exciting aim to produce, unassisted,
a representation as like as he can to one subsequently
sketched on the glass. Thus, without the unintelligent,
mechanical practice of copying other drawings, but
by a method at once simple and attractive—rational,
yet not abstract—a familiarity with the
linear appearances of things, and a faculty of rendering
them, may be step by step acquired. To which
advantages add these:—that even thus early
the pupil learns, almost unconsciously, the true theory
of a picture (namely, that it is a delineation of
objects as they appear when projected on a plane placed
between them and the eye); and that when he reaches
a fit age for commencing scientific perspective, he
is already thoroughly acquainted with the facts which
form its logical basis.
As exhibiting a rational mode of conveying primary conceptions in geometry, we cannot do better than quote the following passage from Mr. Wyse:—
“A child has been in the habit of using cubes for arithmetic; let him use them also for the elements of geometry. I would begin with solids, the reverse of the usual plan. It saves all the difficulty of absurd definitions, and bad explanations on points, lines, and surfaces, which are nothing but abstractions.... A cube presents many of the principal elements of geometry; it at once exhibits points, straight lines, parallel lines, angles, parallelograms, etc., etc. These cubes are divisible into various parts. The pupil has already been familiarised with such divisions in numeration, and he now proceeds to a comparison of their several parts, and of the relation of these parts to each other.... From thence he advances to globes, which furnish him with elementary notions of the circle, of curves generally, etc., etc.