we may establish four sections of the subject before
us: these are (1) the anatomy, (2) the embryology,
and (3) “palaeontology” of mind, and (4)
an inquiry into the way nature deals with the psychical
characteristics of organisms in accomplishing their
evolution. To specify more particularly, it is
possible in the first place to compare the activities
belonging to the category of mental and nervous operations,
displayed by man and other organisms, and the results
form the subject of comparative descriptive psychology;
the second division, namely, developmental or genetic
psychology, deals with the sequence of events in the
life of a single individual by which the infantile
and adolescent types of mind become adult intellectuality;
in the third place, in speaking of the palaeontology
of mind, the phrase is used to refer to the varied
and changing mental abilities of human races in historic
and prehistoric times as they may be demonstrated
and determined by the evidences of the culture of such
earlier epochs. In considering the matter of method,
the questions are whether variation, inheritance,
and selection are as real in the world of mental phenomena
as they are in the material world, and whether the
laws are the same or similar in the two cases.
We shall learn how the results of such studies prove
with convincing clearness, first, that the contents
of the individual mind and of the minds of various
human races are truly the products of natural evolution,
and second, that the human mind differs only in degree
from that of lower organisms, and not in kind or fundamental
nature.
* * * *
*
When the operations of human mental life are examined,
they include what are called processes of reason
as apparently distinctive elements. The lower
mammalia exhibit a simpler order of “mentality”
denoted intelligence, while the nervous processes
of still simpler forms are called instinctive
and reflex activities. These are the terms
of the comparative array of psychology which are to
be separately examined and classified, and to be brought
into an evolutionary sequence if common-sense directs
us to do so.
Let us begin our comparative study with an example
of the simplest animals that consist of only a single
cell, such as the little protozoon Amoeba.
We have become familiar with this organism as one that
carries on all of the vital functions within the limits
of a single structural unit; it is a mass of protoplasm
enclosing a nucleus, and as a biological individual
it must perform all of the eight tasks that are essential
for life. It does not possess a digestive tract,
but it does digest; it does not have breathing organs,
but it does respire; and it is particularly noteworthy
that it must coordinate the different activities of
its parts, and maintain definite relations with the
environment, even though its coordination and sensation
are not accomplished by any special parts that would