of Iago’s character—“the very
pulse of the machine.” He describes his
Circe de la Mothe-Valois as a practical dramatic poet
or playwright at least in lieu of play-writer:
while indicating how and wherefore, with all her constructive
skill and rhythmic art in action, such genius as hers
so differs from the genius of Shakespeare that she
undeniably could not have written a Hamlet.
Neither could Iago have written an Othello.
(From this theorem, by the way, a reasoner or a casuist
benighted enough to prefer articulate poets to inarticulate,
Shakespeare to Cromwell, a fair Vittoria Colonna to
a “foul Circe-Megaera,” and even such a
strategist as Homer to such a strategist as Frederic-William,
would not illogically draw such conclusions or infer
such corollaries as might result in opinions hardly
consonant with the Teutonic-Titanic evangel of the
preacher who supplied him with his thesis.) “But
what he can do, that he will”: and if it
be better to make a tragedy than to write one, to act
a poem than to sing it, we must allow to Iago a station
in the hierarchy of poets very far in advance of his
creator’s. None of the great inarticulate
may more justly claim place and precedence. With
all his poetic gift, he has no poetic weakness.
Almost any creator but his would have given him some
grain of spite or some spark of lust after Desdemona.
To Shakespeare’s Iago she is no more than is
a rhyme to another and articulate poet. {179} His
stanza must at any rate and at all costs be polished:
to borrow the metaphor used by Mr. Carlyle in apologetic
illustration of a royal hero’s peculiar system
of levying recruits for his colossal brigade.
He has within him a sense or conscience of power
incomparable: and this power shall not be left,
in Hamlet’s phrase, “to fust in him unused.”
A genuine and thorough capacity for human lust or
hate would diminish and degrade the supremacy of his
evil. He is almost as far above or beyond vice
as he is beneath or beyond virtue. And this
it is that makes him impregnable and invulnerable.
When once he has said it, we know as well as he that
thenceforth he never will speak word. We could
smile almost as we can see him to have smiled at Gratiano’s
most ignorant and empty threat, being well assured
that torments will in no wise ope his lips: that
as surely and as truthfully as ever did the tortured
philosopher before him, he might have told his tormentors
that they did but bruise the coating, batter the crust,
or break the shell of Iago. Could we imagine
a far other lost spirit than Farinata degli Uberti’s
endowed with Farinata’s might of will, and transferred
from the sepulchres of fire to the dykes of Malebolge,
we might conceive something of Iago’s attitude
in hell—of his unalterable and indomitable
posture for all eternity. As though it were
possible and necessary that in some one point the
extremities of all conceivable good and of all imaginable
evil should meet and mix together in a new “marriage
of heaven and hell,” the action in passion of
the most devilish among all the human damned could
hardly be other than that of the most godlike among
all divine saviours—the figure of Iago
than a reflection by hell-fire of the figure of Prometheus.