and not any other letters. If that cognitional
act had for its object the spho/t/a—i.e.
something different from the letters of the given word—then
those letters would be excluded from it just as much
as the letters of any other word. But as this
is not the case, it follows that that final comprehensive
act of cognition is nothing but an act of remembrance
which has the letters of the word for its object.—Our
opponent has asserted above that the letters of a
word being several cannot form the object of one mental
act. But there he is wrong again. The ideas
which we have of a row, for instance, or a wood or
an army, or of the numbers ten, hundred, thousand,
and so on, show that also such things as comprise
several unities can become the objects of one and the
same cognitional act. The idea which has for
its object the word as one whole is a derived one,
in so far as it depends on the determination of one
sense in many letters[203]; in the same way as the
idea of a wood, an army, and so on. But—our
opponent may here object—if the word were
nothing else but the letters which in their aggregate
become the object of one mental act, such couples
of words as jara and raja or pika and kapi would not
be cognised as different words; for here the same letters
are presented to consciousness in each of the words
constituting one couple.—There is indeed,
we reply, in both cases a comprehensive consciousness
of the same totality of letters; but just as ants
constitute the idea of a row only if they march one
after the other, so the letters also constitute the
idea of a certain word only if they follow each other
in a certain order. Hence it is not contrary to
reason that the same letters are cognised as different
words, in consequence of the different order in which
they are arranged.
The hypothesis of him who maintains that the letters
are the word may therefore be finally formulated as
follows. The letters of which a word consists—assisted
by a certain order and number—have, through
traditional use, entered into a connexion with a definite
sense. At the time when they are employed they
present themselves as such (i.e. in their definite
order and number) to the buddhi, which, after having
apprehended the several letters in succession, finally
comprehends the entire aggregate, and they thus unerringly
intimate to the buddhi their definite sense.
This hypothesis is certainly simpler than the complicated
hypothesis of the grammarians who teach that the spho/t/a
is the word. For they have to disregard what
is given by perception, and to assume something which
is never perceived; the letters apprehended in a definite
order are said to manifest the spho/t/a, and the spho/t/a
in its turn is said to manifest the sense.
Or let it even be admitted that the letters are different
ones each time they are pronounced; yet, as in that
case we necessarily must assume species of letters
as the basis of the recognition of the individual
letters, the function of conveying the sense which
we have demonstrated in the case of the (individual)
letters has then to be attributed to the species.