is understood thereby, it would be improper to assume
them to have a different sense; for that would involve
the fault of abandoning the direct statements of the
text in favour of mere assumptions. Nor can we
conclude the purport of these passages to be the intimation
of the nature of agents, divinities, &c. (connected
with acts of religious duty); for there are certain
scriptural passages which preclude all actions, actors,
and fruits, as, for instance, B/ri/. Up.
II, 4, 13, ‘Then by what should he see whom?’
(which passage intimates that there is neither an
agent, nor an object of action, nor an instrument.)
Nor again can Brahman, though it is of the nature
of an accomplished thing, be the object of perception
and the other means of knowledge; for the fact of
everything having its Self in Brahman cannot be grasped
without the aid of the scriptural passage ‘That
art thou’ (Ch. Up. VI, 8, 7).
Nor can it rightly be objected that instruction is
purportless if not connected with something either
to be striven after or shunned; for from the mere
comprehension of Brahman’s Self, which is not
something either to be avoided or endeavoured after,
there results cessation of all pain, and thereby the
attainment of man’s highest aim. That passages
notifying certain divinities, and so on, stand in
subordinate relation to acts of devout meditation
mentioned in the same chapters may readily be admitted.
But it is impossible that Brahman should stand in an
analogous relation to injunctions of devout meditation,
for if the knowledge of absolute unity has once arisen
there exists no longer anything to be desired or avoided,
and thereby the conception of duality, according to
which we distinguish actions, agents, and the like,
is destroyed. If the conception of duality is
once uprooted by the conception of absolute unity,
it cannot arise again, and so no longer be the cause
of Brahman being looked upon as the complementary
object of injunctions of devotion. Other parts
of the Veda may have no authority except in so far
as they are connected with injunctions; still it is
impossible to impugn on that ground the authoritativeness
of passages conveying the knowledge of the Self; for
such passages have their own result. Nor, finally,
can the authoritativeness of the Veda be proved by
inferential reasoning so that it would be dependent
on instances observed elsewhere. From all which
it follows that the Veda possesses authority as a means
of right knowledge of Brahman.
Here others raise the following objection:—Although the Veda is the means of gaining a right knowledge of Brahman, yet it intimates Brahman only as the object of certain injunctions, just as the information which the Veda gives about the sacrificial post, the ahavaniya-fire and other objects not known from the practice of common life is merely supplementary to certain injunctions[69]. Why so? Because the Veda has the purport of either instigating to action or restraining from it.