“Democracy,” which he reprinted from his
first work on Foreign Schools in 1861, where it had
appeared as an Introduction. The juxtaposition
is by no means uninteresting or uninstructive, though
perhaps it is not entirely favourable to the idea
of Mr Arnold’s development as a
zoon politicon.
It has been said before that his earliest political
writing is a good deal less fantastic and more sane
than that of his middle period, and though “the
last of life for which the first was made” was
now restoring to him much of his power in this direction,
yet he was always much joined to idols in matters
political. In grasp “Democracy” does
not quite come up to its rather ambitious title; and
a moment’s thought will show why. In 1861
Democracy was a very academic subject. All projects
for further Parliamentary Reform had failed utterly
in England; and nobody dreamt of what the next five
or six years would bring. In France there was
what looked like a crushing military despotism:
in other Continental countries the repression which
had followed the outbreaks of 1848-49 was only just
being relaxed, or not relaxed at all. American
democracy had not had its second baptism of Civil
War. The favourite fancies about the respective
ethos of aristocracy, of the middle-class,
and of the lower do indeed appear, but for the most
part Mr Arnold confines himself to the simple question
of State interference, for which in his own subject
of education he was so anxious, and which he would
gladly have seen extended. It has been more than
once remarked already that he may justly be regarded
as a politician of more seriousness than he has here
been represented as possessing, if espousing the cause
of the things which actually happen is taken as the
criterion. For State interference has grown and
is growing every day. But then it may be held—and
as a matter of principle he would not himself have
contested it—that a man’s politics
should be directed, not by what he thinks will happen,
but by what he thinks ought to happen. And some
of us, while not in love by any means with the middle-class
Liberal ideas of 1830-1860, think that the saving
grace of that day that is dead was precisely its objection
to State interference.
“Equality,” which follows, and which starts
what might be called at the time of the book its contemporary
interest, is much more far-reaching and of greater
curiosity; indeed, it may perhaps be held to be the
most curious, in a certain sense, of all its author’s
writings, and to give, in a not fully satisfactory
but suggestive fashion, a key to his complex character
which is supplied by no other of his essays.
That there was (in no silly or derogatory sense of
an often absurdly used word) a slightly un-English
side to that character, few acute judges would deny.
But its results, in the greater part of the works,
are so diffused, and, as it were, subterranean, that
they are difficult to extract and concentrate.
Here we seem to get the spirit much nearer proof.