but is always becoming” ([Greek: aei gignetai]),
he delivered a text, out of which we may derive something;
for he destroys by it not all practical, but all speculative
notions of cause and effect. The whole series
of things, as they appear to us, must be contemplated
in time, that is in succession, and we conceive or
suppose intervals between one state of things and another
state of things, so that there is priority and sequence,
and interval, and Being, and a ceasing to Be, and
beginning and ending. But there is nothing of
the kind in the Nature of Things. It is an everlasting
continuity (iv. 45; vii. 75). When Antoninus
speaks of generation (x. 26), he speaks of one cause
([Greek: aitia]) acting, and then another cause
taking up the work, which the former left in a certain
state, and so on; and we might perhaps conceive that
he had some notion like what has been called “the
self-evolving power of nature;” a fine phrase
indeed, the full import of which I believe that the
writer of it did not see, and thus he laid himself
open to the imputation of being a follower of one of
the Hindu sects, which makes all things come by evolution
out of nature or matter, or out of something which
takes the place of Deity, but is not Deity. I
would have all men think as they please, or as they
can, and I only claim the same freedom which I give.
When a man writes anything, we may fairly try to find
out all that his words must mean, even if the result
is that they mean what he did not mean; and if we find
this contradiction, it is not our fault, but his misfortune.
Now Antoninus is perhaps somewhat in this condition
in what he says (x. 26), though he speaks at the end
of the paragraph of the power which acts, unseen by
the eyes, but still no less clearly. But whether
in this passage (x. 26) lie means that the power is
conceived to be in the different successive causes
([Greek: aitiai]), or in something else, nobody
can tell. From other passages, however, I do
collect that his notion of the phenomena of the universe
is what I have stated. The Deity works unseen,
if we may use such language, and perhaps I may, as
Job did, or he who wrote the book of Job. “In
him we live and move and are,” said St. Paul
to the Athenians; and to show his hearers that this
was no new doctrine, he quoted the Greek poets.
One of these poets was the Stoic Cleauthes, whose
noble hymn to Zeus, or God, is an elevated expression
of devotion and philosophy. It deprives Nature
of her power, and puts her under the immediate government
of the Deity.
“Thee all this heaven, which whirls around the
earth,
Obeys, and willing follows where thou leadest.
Without thee, God, nothing is done on earth,
Nor in the ethereal realms, nor in the sea,
Save what the wicked through their folly do.”
Antoninus’ conviction of the existence of a divine power and government was founded on his perception of the order of the universe. Like Socrates (Xen. Mem., iv. 3, 13, etc.) he says that though we cannot see the forms of divine powers, we know that they exist because we see their works.